The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. Incentives and Aggregate Shocks Author(s): Christopher Phelan Source: The Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 61, No. 4 (Oct., 1994), pp. 681-700 Published by: The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297914 Accessed: 03/03/2010 03:49 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=resl. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Economic Studies. http://www.jstor.org Reviewof EconomicStudies(1994) 61, 681-700 ? 1994The Reviewof EconomicStudiesLimited Incentives and 0034-6527/94/00330681$02.00 Aggregate Shocks CHRISTOPHERPHELAN Northwestern University and University of Wisconsin-Madison First version received August 1992; final version accepted May 1994 (Eds.) theoryof thedynamicsof the distributionof consumpThispaperpresentsan incentive-based tion in the presenceof aggregateshocks.Thepaperbuildson the modelsconcerningthedistribution of incomeor consumptionand incentiveproblemsof Green(1987), Thomasand Worrall(1991), PhelanandTownsend(1991),and Atkesonand Lucas(1992).By incorporatingaggregateproduction shocks,the modelallowsan examinationof the interactionsbetweenindividualand aggregate consumptionseries given incompleteinsurance.Further,the methodologyoutlinedallows the incorporationof incentiveconsiderationsto macroeconomicenvironmentssimilarto Rogerson (1988) and Hansen(1985). 1. INTRODUCTION This paper presents an incentive-basedtheory of the dynamicsof the distributionof consumptionin the presenceof aggregateshocks.Its methodologicalaccomplishmentsare two-fold: First, it displays a method for explicit considerationof aggregateshocks in incentiveeconomiessuch as those of Green (1987), Phelan dynamicgeneral-equilibrium and Townsend(1991) and Atkeson and Lucas (1992). Second, it displaysa method for explicitconsiderationof incentiveconditionsin macroeconomicenvironments,where,for reasonsof tractability,incentiveconditionsare usuallyignored.One interpretationof the limited-insuranceversion of the environmentpresentedhere is an incentive-constrained, unemploymentmodels of Hansen (1985) and Rogerson (1988) which, for reasons of tractability,assumefull insuranceover unemploymentrisk. In the model presented,each agent'sobservableoutcomesare a functionof his unobservablelevel of effort, an unobservableidiosyncraticshock, and a publicly observed aggregateshock. While risk-averseagents would wish to pool (and thus insureagainst) their idiosyncraticrisk, such completeinsuranceis not feasibledue to the unobservable effort.Becauseof the non-incentivecompatibilityof full-insurance,highereffortlevelsare achievedby makingeachagent'sconsumptiona functionof his currentandpast observable outcomes.Agentswith favourablecurrentoutcomesreceiveboth highercurrentand future consumption.This contingencyof individualconsumptionon individualoutcomescauses the consumptionof ex ante identicalagents to differover time. Further,since individual outcomesare also affectedby aggregateshocks, the aggregateshocks not only affect the averagelevel of consumptionas in a single-agentmodel, but the efficientdistributionof consumptionas well. To this date, the only analyticallytractablemodel available to make predictions regardingthe dynamicsof the distributionof consumptionin the presenceof aggregate shocks is the full-informationor complete-marketsframework.With aggregablepreferences, such an economy reducesto an economywith a single representativeagent. After economy, one can make predictionsregardingdistribusolving the representative-agent economy relativelystraighttions in economieswhich reduceto the representative-agent forwardly.Papersby Mace (1991), Cochrane(1991), and Townsend(1994) examinethe 681 682 REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES relationshipbetweenindividualconsumptionseriesand aggregateconsumptionseriesin light of the predictionsof full-information,complete-marketmodels. The generalresult of these papers is that the full insuranceimplicationsof full informationmodels are rejected.Thisimpliesthe needfor modelswhichallowricherinteractionsbetweenaggregate and idiosyncraticshocks on consumptionlevels. Solvingdynamic,stochasticmodels which make predictionsregardingconsumption distributionsis difficultif one straysfrom assumptionswhich allow reductionto a representativeagent.With more than one type of agent at a given time, marketclearingprices generallydependon the entiredistributionof agent types. In modelswherethe evolution of the distributionof typesis endogenous,thiscausesintractability.Onewayof interpreting the aggregationresultswhichallow the reductionof an economyto a singlerepresentative agent is that they show one set of specialcircumstanceswhich cause distributionsnot to affectprices. An accomplishmentof this paper is the derivationof a differentset of assumptions which allow predictions regardingdistributionswith the full-informationassumption relaxed,but still allow the model to be solved. While the predictionsof this model differ substantiallyfromthe testable(and rejected)full-insurancepredictionsof the full-information model, they are not without content. Specifically,I show that like the dynamic, incentive-basedmodel of Green(1987) whichis void of productionand aggregateshocks, individualconsumptionlevels follow a processwhich is the sum of an i.i.d. term and a term which follows a randomwalk. Second, I show that while individualconsumption changesare not perfectlycorrelatedas with full-insurance,they are positivelycorrelated acrossindividuals,since they dependon a commonaggregateshock. Finally,I show that the characteristicsof the cross-sectionaldistributionof consumptionitself will dependon the historyof aggregateshocks.I show that in contrastto the full-informationframework wherethe currentaggregateshock alone determinesthe distributionof consumption,the frictionsassumedherecausethe predicteddistributionof consumptionto follow a Markov process. Thispaperbuildson the modelsconcerningthe distributionof incomeor consumption and incentiveproblemsof Green (1987), Thomas and Worrall (1991), Phelan (1994), Phelanand Townsend(1991), and Atkeson and Lucas(1992). Unlike each of the papers except Phelan (1994), the long-rundistributionof consumptionis not degeneratedue to the overlappinggenerationsframeworkadoptedhere. Banerjeeand Newman (1991) also considerthe questionof consumptiondistributionand risk-bearingand developa model with a non-degeneratelong-rundistribution.They do this by assumingfamily dynasties with bequestmotiveswhereconsumptionis boundedfrom below by the fact that agents arelimitedin the amountof debt theycan pass to theirchildrenand above by assumptions causing the incentiveproblem to disappearfor agents with high enough wealth levels. Taub (1990) considerslinear incentiveschemesin an economy with moral hazard and aggregateshocks. The model in this paper can also be consideredan incentive-constrained, limitedinsurancemodel of unemploymentsimilarto the full-insuranceunemploymentmodels of Hansen (1985) and Rogerson (1988). Thus while the model presentedin this paper is simplerthat that of Hansen on dimensionsother than the considerationof incentives (specifically,the modelin thispaperdoes not havecapital)themethodsin thispapershould be seen as encouragingto macroeconomictheoristswho wish to incorporateincentivesor dynamiccontractinginto models with both individualand aggregaterisk. Section2 presentsthe technologyand preferencesassumedin this model. Section 3 presentsa fairly lengthy constructionof an equilibrium.The key of this section is an PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 683 ability to show that marketpricescan be representedby vectorswhich remainconstant over time, or which are independentof the distributionof types in the population.The aggregateshock affects realizedprices only by picking out elementsof these constant vectors.(For example,therewill be a time-independent vectorassociatingeach aggregate shock with a one-periodinterestrate. The realizedinterestrate is determinedonly by the currentrealizedaggregateshock.) Section4 discussesthe characteristics of this equilibrium as comparedto the characteristicsof the same model but given full information.Section 5 discussesoptima, using an extensionof the techniquesof Atkeson and Lucas (1992). Here the constructedequilibriumof Section 3 is shown to be optimal, and a planning problemis derivedto find the plan associatedwith the constructedequilibriumwithout searchingfor market-clearingprices.Section6 concludes. 2. THE MODEL The economy consists of overlappinggenerationsof identical agents. Each generation consists of a continuumof agents and is of equal size (unity) at birth. At the beginning of each date, each agent takes an unobservableaction aEA where the set A is assumed orderedand finite.This action resultsin a publiclyobservedoutput qe Q (Q orderedand finite) accordingto the non-zeroprobabilityfunction P(qla, 0) where Ce0 (0 ordered and finite) is a publicly observedaggregateshock drawn independentlyover time with probabilityZ(0). It is importantto note that 0 is observedafterthe actionis taken.After output q occurs,consumptionoccurs. Let Y-=R denote the set of possible consumption amounts.After each period,agents are assumedto die with probability(1 -A), independent of age, and thus the size of the t-aged generationequals A''. Assume at the first calendardate that thereexists the steady-statenumberof agents, 1/(1 -A). The calendar dates are numberedr= 1, ..., ooc. These variablescan be interpretedstraightforwardlyas a model where individuals can "sleepon thejob" (take low efforta). In this interpretation,q representsthe physical, stochasticallydeterminedwork outputof the agentmeasuredin units of the consumption good and P(qla, 0) representsthe probabilityof each of these output levels for a given level of effortand aggregateshock. Presumably,low effortlevels increasethe probability of low outputs.An alternativeinterpretationis to considerq to be the qualityof a match between a worker and a firm (again measuredin units of the consumptiongood and representingthe deterministicproductivityof the workerin that match) and a to be the unobservableefforttakenby an agent to find a productivematch.Thus, one can consider an incentive-constrained unemploymentmodel by letting q take on two levels: employment,with a correspondinghigh productivityq, and unemployment,with a corresponding zero or low productivityq. The function P(qla, 0) is then the probabilityof a given employmentstate for an agent given the effortlevel of the agent at findinga job, a, and the aggregatestate 0. At the beginningof his life, each agent entersinto a bindinglifetimecontractwith a financialintermediaryor firm, in the case of equilibria,or the social planner,in the case of optima.The contractspecifiesfor each date in the agent'slife his action level a and his consumptionc. The contractmaymakeconsumptionor efforta functionof all information availablein the economy at the appropriatetime. Agents care about their expecteddiscountedstreamof point-in-timeutilitiesover consumptionand effortwherethe common point-in-timeutility function U(a, c) is the constant absolute risk aversionspecification 684 REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES U: A x Y-+R_ such that U(a, c) = -exp (-y(c - v(a))), wherev(a) is any increasingfunction. Agents discountthe futureusing the constantdiscountparameter 1< 1. Define the set of possibleex-anteutilities W_ R_. 3. EQUILIBRIA This section constructsan equilibriumwhere all potential tradingis betweeninfinitelylived financialintermediariesor "firms"which exist from the first calendardate. When agentsare born they are offeredlifetimecontractsby firmsand acceptwhatevercontract gives them the highestexpecteddiscountedutility w from the perspectiveof birth.This is the only markettransactionindividualsmay ever engage in. From then on they simply follow the contract.In effect,agents "sell themselves"to a firmfor life. Enoughcommitment is assumedbetweenfirmsand individualsfor such contractsto be always binding. While for now this is simply an assertedrestrictionof the interactionbetweenagents in the economy, it will later be shown to non-restrictivein the sense that if the possibility for such commitmentexists, it is optimal for society or the contractsthemselvesto bar agentsfrom trade. Firms, on the other hand, can trade the consumptiongood across dates and states at prices they take to be given. For a given promisedutility w0, the firm'sproblemis to maximizearbitrageprofits (or, as it will be stated later, to minimizearbitragelosses). Firms do not have preferences.They take as given prices for date and state contingent consumptionin termsof a numerairegood and use these pricesto transformprofitsand losses at variousdates and states into a single number.Again, only firmsoperatein the contingentclaimsand creditmarkets.Transactionsin these marketsare assumedobservable and thus barringindividualsfrom tradeis enforceable.' Optimal contracts I now considerthe questionof what kind of contractsfirmswill offer to agents. Instead of assumingtime-zeromarketsallowingfirmsto tradedate-and state-contingentconsumption, I assume a sufficient set of spot markets. Let B,(0,lJ00... , O,'-1) be the spot price at the beginningof date t of 0,-contingentconsumption,in termsof date t non-contingent consumption(thus EZ.B,(Ol00, . . ., of- 1)= 1). That is, I assumea spot insurancemarket at date t that allowsfirmsto buy and sell 0,-contingentconsumptionbefore 0, is realized. For intertemporal trade, I assume a credit market. Let S,(0,l 0, . . ., O- 1) be the spot priceat the end of period t (after 0, is realized)of date t + 1 non-contingentconsumption in termsof current(0,-contingent)consumption.Thesespot marketssufficientlyreplicate the tradingopportunitiesof a completeset of time-zeromarkets. The problemof findingefficientcontractscan be solvedusing recursivetechniquesif these spot prices are independentof history and depend only on the currentaggregate shock 0, and can thus be writtensimplyas vectorsB(0) and 3(0). This is trueunderany framework(as does this one if not for economywhich reducesto a representative-agent unobservableeffort),but at this point I have given no reasonswhy this shouldbe the case for this economy. Nevertheless,it is still a well definedquestion to ask how contracts wouldlook if thesevectorsof spotpriceswereconstant.I will laterconstructan equilibrium wherethese vectorsare, in fact, constant. 1. Note that unlike most overlapping-generations models the traders here, the firms, have access to all markets. PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 685 Optimalcontractsare recursivein the sense that the expecteddiscountedutility of an agent from any point time on (say w) sufficientlysummarizesall informationabout that agent relevantfor constructinga continuationcontract between the firm and the agent.2When an agent is born, the cost to a firm of contractingwith the agent is solely a functionof the level of utility w the firmpromisesthe agent. (Here, cost is in termsof presentnon-contingentconsumption.)An agent owed a high expecteddiscountedutility (say wo)will cost more than an agent owed a low wo. After the agent'sfirst day of life, he will have an expecteddiscountedutility (say w1)of followingthe contracthe signedat birth. Since actions and transfersunder this contract can depend on the output of the agent in his first period of life, this expecteddiscountedutility w1 will in generaldiffer from the expecteddiscountedutilitywothe agenthad when he signedthe contract.Nevertheless,from the perspectiveof the firm,the one-period-oldagent looks no differentthan a newbornagent who was given an initialutilitypromiseof wi. It costs the firmthe same to providea lifetimecontractto an agent initiallypromisedw1as it does to continue a contractthat providesthe agent with a continuationutility of w1. Given that the firmconsidersthe expecteddiscountedutilityof the agentto be a state variable,its choice variablesare as follows. The firmchoosesa functiona(w): W-+A,that specifiesthe recommendedaction as a function of the agent's expectedutility from the currentdate on. Likewise,the firmchoosesfor each we Wa consumptiontransferfunction Y(q,01w):Q x 0-*R which again dependson the agent's expecteddiscountedutility at the beginningof the period,and also the agent'scurrentoutputq and the currentaggregate shock 0. The currentperiod output of the agent and the aggregateshock are known to the firm at the time of the consumptiontransferbut not at the time actions are recommended. Finally, the firm chooses for each we Wa function W'(q, 01w): Q x 0-* Wwhich specifiesthe utilitypromiseto the agent from the perspectiveof the next period. The set of functions [a(w), Y(q, 01w), W'(q, 01w)] completely specifies a lifetime con- tract for an agent with an initial utility of w0. His recommendedaction on his first day of life is a(wo)and his consumptionis Y(qo,Oolwo),whereqois the agent'soutput on his firstday of life and 0 is the aggregateshock for this date. The promisedutility function W'(q,Olw) then generates the contract for the next period of life. For instance, a( W'(qo, Oolwo)) is the agent's recommended action in his second period of life, and Y(ql, 0OiW'(qo,Oolwo))is the agent'sconsumptionin his second periodof life. Without loss of generality,I can split the consumptiontransferfunction Y into a transferwhich does not depend on q or 0, z(w), and a transferwhich can depend on q and 0, y(q, 01w), so that Y(q, 01w) = z(w) +y(q, 01w). Likewise, I can allow the promise generatingfunction W' to be stated as a componentw'(q,Olw)which may dependon q 2. The proofthat the continuationutilityof the agentw sufficientlysummarizeshis history(moreformally presentedin Spearand Srivastava(1987) and Phelanand Townsend(1991)) can be sketchedas follows.One first formulatescontractsas specifyingthe work efforta and consumptionc of an agent at each point in time as a functionof the agent'sentire output historyas well as the historyof aggregateshocks and consideran efficientcontractin this (large) space. After any given historyh, the agent will have a utility w(h) associated with continuingthe contract.One then considersgiving the firm a chance to re-optimizeor choose a new continuationcontractsubjectto incentivecompatibilityconditionsand a constraintthat the agent'scontinuation utilityremainconstant.However,one can showthatanynewcontinuationcontractcouldhavebeenincorporated into the originalcontractwithoutupsettingthe incentivecompatibilityfor the originalcontractor the ex ante utilitythe agent associatedwith the originalcontract.This impliesthat the firmcannot lowerits continuation costs by reoptimizing.Any potentialgain from re-optimizationwould have alreadybeen incorporatedinto the originalcontract.This impliesthat if afterhistoryh, the firmwereto "forget"the historyh, but rememberthe agent'sutilityw(h)associatedwiththis history,the firmcouldrecoverthe continuationplanfromh by minimizing its continuationcosts of providingan incentivecompatiblecontinuationcontractsubjectto the agentreceiving Thusthe agent'sutilitycontainsall the informationnecessaryto recoverthe continuacontinuationutilitywv(h). tion contractor sufficientlysummarizeshistoryh. REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES 686 and 0 scaledby exp (-yz(w)), or W'(q, 0jw)=exp (-yz(w))w'(q, 01w). For now, simply take this non-contingentpaymentz and the scalingof utility promisesas harmlessextra degreesof freedomin the firm'schoiceproblem.The non-contingentpaymentz can always be chosen to equal to zero and thus exp (- yz) =1. Further,for z equal to any non-zero constant,the functionsy and w' can be chosen to "undo"the effectof the non-zeroz. The firm is not free to pick just any contract. For an agent who was promiseda specificexpecteddiscountedutilityof w, the firmmustpick policies[z, a, y(q, 0), w'(q,0)] which actually deliver this expected utility. This can be expressedin the form of the promise-keepingconstraint W=Z EQ {-exp (-y(z+y(q, 0) - v(a))) + fA exp (-yz)w'(q, 0)}P(qla, 0)Z(0). (1) Equation(1) is the lifetimeexpecteddiscountedutilityof the agent from the beginningof the periodgiven that the utilitypromiseexp (-yz)w'(q, 0) is actuallydeliveredgiven that the agent lives to see the next period. The firmmust also respectthe unobservabilityof actions,again for each we W.This is expressedas incentiveconstraintsthat for all aeA, E. EQ {-exp (-y(z+y(q, >_,EQ 0)- v(a))) +f3A exp (-yz)w'(q, 0)}P(qla, 0)Z(0) {-exp (-y(z +y(q, 0)- v(a))) + A exp (-yz)w'(q, 0)}P(qla, 0)Z(0). (2) The right-handside of equation(2) is the lifetimeexpecteddiscountedutilityof following deviationaction a, again given that futureutilitypromisesare kept. Let C*(w)denotethe cost in termsof currentnon-contingentconsumptionof providing an expecteddiscountedutilityw to an agent.Optimalcontractscan be foundby noting that C*(w) is a fixed point of the operator T defined by the following programming problem.The operatorT takes as given a cost functiongoverningutilitypromisesmade today for tomorrowon, and generatesthe cost functiongoverningutility promisesfrom the perspectiveof today. The objectiveof the programmeis to minimizethe value of net consumptiontransfersin termsof currentnon-contingentconsumption,or, (TC)(w)- min Y, Q{z +y(q, 0)-q z,a,y(q,0),Wv(q,f0) + S(0)AC(exp (-yz)w'(q, 0)))P(qla, 0)B(0) (3) subjectto the promise-keepingconstraint(1), and the incentiveconstraintsrepresented by (2). It is importantto note that while q is a randomvariablefor a given agent, the innersummationover q in the objectivefunction(3)-the expectedvalueof the expression insidethe bracketsgiven 0-is knownwith certaintygiven 0. Firmsdo not face risk over q realizationssince they can contractwith a positive mass of agents and thus P(qla, 0) representsthe certainfractionof agents who realizeq. Thus the inner sum is the certain cost, for a given 0 realization,of the plan [z, a, y(q, 0), w'(q,0)]. Summingover 0 and weightingby the prices B(O) gives the total cost of the plan in terms in currentnoncontingentconsumption. The exponentialutility functionallows a substantialsimplificationof this programming problem. The trick is to use the unconditionalpayment z to handle the utility constraint,and the conditionalpaymenty(q, 0) and promisesw'(q,0) to handlethe incentive constraints.This is justifiedas follows. PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 687 In the incentiveconstraint(2), one can pull the expressionexp (-yz) outsideof both summationson each side of the inequalityand cancel, giving Z ZQ {-exp (-y(y(q, >, 0) - v(a))) + fAw'(q, 0)}P(qla, 0)Z(0) (-y(y(q, 0) - v(&)))+ fAw'(q, 0)}P(qJ , 0)Z(0). Q {-exp I (4) This shows that if a contractis incentivecompatiblegiven one constantpaymentz, it is incentivecompatiblefor all constantpaymentsz. In the promise-keepingconstraint(1), one can again pull out from the right-hand side the expressionexp (-yz). If this is set equalto -w, or z(w)= -log (-w)/y, this gives (1) as -1 =E. YQ{-exp (-y(y(q, 0)- v(a))) +/3Aw'(q,0)}P(qJa,O)Z(O), (5) thus removingz and w from the constraintset. The intuitionhere is that (5) insuresthat if z = 0, the functionsy(q, 0) and w'(q,0) deliveran expectedutility of -1. If the policies [a, y(q, 0), w'(q,0)] satisfy (5), this along with the assumptionthat z(w) -log (-w)/y insures that the collection [z, a, y(q, 0), w'(q,0)] satisfies the original promise-keeping constraint(1) for any w. This ability to state the constraintsindependentof the promise w allows the followingresult. Lemma1. (1) Thefunction C*(w) takes theform Q)- = 1I 1 -6A -log (-w) + H~ Y (6) average whereH is a constant(C(-1)) and -L S(0)B(0) is theprice-weighted (over 0) of theprice of one-periodaheadconsumption,3(0). (2) There exist efficientpolicies (a, y(q, 0), w'(q,0)) which do not dependon the promisedutilityw. Proof First, the true cost function C* can be shown to be a continuousfunction which everywherelies betweentwo particularfunctionsof the form in (6). The first, a lowerboundof the truecost function,is the cost functionassociatedwith the sameproblem but withoutthe incentiveconstraint.The second,an upperboundof the truecost function, is the cost functionwhere the action a is constrainedto equal the lowest elementof A. Each of these problemsis static, and thus the true cost functionsfor these problemscan be shown to take the form of (6), with (say), H equallingthe constant term for lower bound, and ft equallingthe constanttermfor the upperbound. The space of continuous functionslyingeverywherebetweenthe boundingfunctionsjust describedis completeand can be normalizedby applyingthe supnorm.Callthis normedvectorspaceS. The operator T can be shown to be a contractionon S by examiningthe objectivefunction (3) and noting that Blackwell'ssufficientconditionshold. The right-handside is monotone in C and T(c+ C) = T(C) + SAc for constantsc. This insuresthat thereis a uniquefixedpoint of T in S. The set of functionsactuallyof the form in (6) constitutea completesubsetof S, say S. Showingthat T maps S to itself completesthe proof. Since z can be set to any constant without harming the minimizedvalue of the objectivefunction,set z equal to the constant -log (-w)/y. Second,considera function REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES 688 CES (and thus of the form in (6)) with constanttermH1.Replacingz with -log (-w)/y in the objectivefunction(3) and substitutingin for C allows us to derive (T)(w)_ 1 1-6A -log (-w)+ 9 y , P(qJa, O)B(O),(7 (7) (0)A -log (-w'(q, '0))1Pa0B0 + min + (G)(6) 0) -q +(?/I( E.Z4Y~~ {Qy(q 0-q+ y 1-SAi a,y(q,69),%'(q,f9) wherethe minimizationis, again,subjectto (5) and (4). Sincethe solutionto the minimization problemin (7) subjectto (5) and (4) is independentof w, the sum of the second and thirdtermson the right-handside of (7) is simplya constant.Thus we have shown that the operatorT preservesthe guessedfrom of C* in the statementof the Lemma.The fact that the minimizationproblemin (7) does not contain w impliesthat the loss-minimizing policiesa*, y*(q, 0) and w'*(q,0) will not dependon w. 11 The true constant (say H*) can be found by using the fact that for the true cost functionC*, T(C*)= C*, and thus the trueconstantH* equals 1/(1 - SA) times the solution to the minimizationproblem in (7). Given this H*, equation (6) is a fixed point of T. The fact that the loss-minimizingpoliciesa*, y*(q, 0) and w'*(q,0) will not depend on w impliesthat all agents receivedthe same recommendedaction a and face the same conditionalpaymentsy*(q, 0). Theirunconditionalpaymentsare determinedby the function z*(w)= -log (-w)/y. Future utilities are determined by the scaling factor exp (-yz*(w)) = -w, multiplied by the common updating function w'*(q, 0). This separa- tion impliesthat one partof the cost-minimizingplanfor the representivefirmis to partially pay the agents in termsof positive and negativeconstant annuities-fixed paymentsthe agent receiveseveryperiod for the rest of his life. (This characteristicis in Green (1987) and Atkeson and Lucas (1992) for optimalplans.) To see this,consideran agentwithstartingutilitywoand thusan initialnon-contingent payment z*(wo)= -log (-wo)/y. This agent's expected utility at the beginning of his secondperiodof life can be writtenw, = -w0w'*(qOga, 00). Hereqois the agent'srealization of q in his first period of life, and 0 is the economy-widerealizationof the aggregate shock for that date. It quickly follows that z(w1) = -log (-wo)/y-log (-w'*(qo, Oo))/y An agent who "draws"qoand 00 in his firstperiod of life is deliveredthe unconditional payment-log (-w'*(qo, Oo))/y consumptionunits in the next periodalong with his original unconditionalpayment-log (-wo)/y. In general,his unconditionalconsumptionpayment at any given period t is the sum of paymentsfor all previousperiods,includinghis initial payment -log (-wo)/y, along with the latest addition -log (-w'*(qt,i, Ot-1))/y. Constructionof constant-price equilibrium Everythingto this point relieson this assumptionthat the vectorsof spot pricesB(6) and 6(0) are actuallyconstant over time. I now turn to constructingan equilibriumwhere this is true.Note that by constantpriceequilibriumI do not mean that realizedpricesare constant,but only that the vectorsthat realizedpricesare drawnfrom are constant. Assumea singleprice-takingrepresentativefirmwhichin everyperiodoffersall newbornagentsa contractwithutilitywo,makesnon-contingentpaymentsz*(w)= -log (-w)/ y to agentswhosecurrentexpectedutilitiesequalw, makescontingentpaymentsaccording to y*(q, 0), and updatesutilitypromisesthroughthe functionw'*(q,0) as in the previous INCENTIVES AND AGGREGATE SHOCKS PHELAN 689 section. That is, assume that the representativefirm adopts policies which are optimal given constantprices.I now look to see if marketscan clear this restriction. For marketsto clear,this representativefirmneeds at all dates and statesto transfer to agents (in aggregate)exactly as much consumptionas the agents produce.Put differently, the aggregatedeficit of the representativefirm (paymentsy+z minus outputs q) must equal zero regardlessof the date or state. The strategyI use is to deriveconditions firmto be constantacross whichfor a givenperiod r cause the deficitof the representative 0 shocks and constant across the consecutivedates T and T + 1. I then show that these conditionsimplythemselvesfor one periodahead,and thusmathematicalinductionimplies the conditionsguaranteeconstantdeficitsfor all dates and states. Lastly,by constraining this deficitto be zero, "marketclearing"conditionsare derivedfor the consumptiongood over dates and states. At the beginningof each period,everythingbut the distributionof promisedutilities in the economyis the same.Let T' be the distributionof promisedutilitiesat date r. This distributionis assumedto have total measure 1/(1 -A), the size of the population.Let D*(Tr, 0) denotethe deficitof the representativefirm(or aggregatedeficit)at date r given distributionT' and realization0 of the aggregateshock given policies [z*, a*, y*(q, 0)]. Lemma 2. Relative deficits across 0 shocks are independent of the distribution of utilities T . That is, for all dates T and distributions Tr, the difference (D*(TPr,0) - D*(Tr, O)) is a function only of the shocks 0Oe9 and Je0. Proof. The aggregatedeficitcan be written D*(Pr, 0)= E (log (W) +y*(q, 0) -q)P(qIa*, o)dTr(w)} ={fJlo > ) d'{PT(w)}+ 1-A {Q {y*(q, 0)-q}P(qja*, 0)}. (8) The separationon the right-handside of (8) occurs because of the separationof optimalpaymentsinto a non-contingentpayment-log (-w)/y whichdependson w and a contingentpaymenty*(q, 0) whichdoes not dependon w. Thus total net paymentsare the total of non-contingentpaymentswhich dependson the distributionof utilitiesT', plus the total of net contingentpaymentswhich dependsonly on the expectedvalue of the net contingentpaymentmultipliedby the numberof agents, 1/(1 -A). Differencing (8) across 0 realizationscausesthe firsttermon the righthand side to cancel,provingthe Lemma. 11 An immediatecorollaryis that if a set of polies [z*, a*, y*(q, 0)] causesthe aggregate deficitD*(PT, 0) to be constantacross 0 realizationsfor one distributionT', then these policieswill inducea constantdeficitacross 0 shocks for all distributionsVPT. While the policies [z*, a*, y*(q, 0)] affect the deficit at date x, the policy w'*(q,0) (along with z*) affectsthe date r + 1 distributionof utilitiesand thus the date r + 1 deficit. Let G*(Tr, 0) denote the date r + 1 distributionof utilitiesgiven the date r distribution T'Pand the date r shock 0 underthe policies [z*, w'*(q, 0)]. Lemma 3. If for a given distribution T'Pat date r, the deficit of the representative firm D*(TQ, or) equals a constant d, regardless of the outcome of or, and iffor any given REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES 690 j, 1, the T + I deficit D*(G*(Tr, Or), OFr+) equals this same constant d, regardless of Or, then the deficit at all future dates (r + 2, T + 3,...) will also equal d, regardless of the outcomesof shocks(Or+I,Or+2,.. )- Proof. This proof is based on mathematicalinduction.I show that if one assumes constantdeficitsacross 0 at date r and this same equal deficit at date r + 1, then these assumptionsimply themselvesone period ahead. The conditionthat the date r deficitequal a constantd regardlessof the outcomeof Or can be stated as, for all Ore-0 D*TPr, Or) log w) +y*(q, -{JWOQr)-q)P(qla*, ={{Jlo -A {Q {y* (q, 0r)-q}P(qja*, dPr(w)}+ $w) Or)dTr(w)} Or)} =d. (9) The requirementthat the date r + 1 deficitequal d regardlessof the outcome of or can be writtenas, for all Or and any given Or+ D*(G*(TPr, Or), Ur? i )) -log (-w) dG*(Tr, Or)(w)} = + I{Q{y*(q0,+1) E, - q}P(qja*, O+)} = d. (10) Condition(10) need hold only for one possible 0r+I becausecondition (9) holding for all 0 impliesthat the expectedvalue of net conditionalpayments(the secondtermon the right-handside of condition(9)) is constantacross 0 realizations.Thus condition(9) holdingfor all 0 impliesthat if (10) holds for any particularvalue of 0r+I it holds for all valuesof 0r+ I The next step in the argumentis to show that if the conditionsin equations (9) and (10) hold for a distributionT', then this impliesthey also hold for each of the possiblesuccessorsof 8T' G*(Tr, 0). Equation (10) is simply a restatementof (9) where the distributionTr has been replacedwith a successordistributionG*(Tr, or) and the currentshock has been set to a particularvalue. Thus the assumptionof conditions(9) and (10) holdingfor T' immediately impliesthat condition (9) holds for each possiblesuccessordistributionG*(Tr, or). To show that equation (10) will also hold for all possible ;Tr+' = G*(Tr, 0) requires some more manipulation.Specifically,if I replacein for the successorfunction G*, the sum of the unconditionalz paymentscan be writtenas -log (-w) dG*e(r, Or)(w) w Y -log (-wo) -log (-wo) + A{{ (ww)*(q, or)) -log(-w) dTr(w)} ~w Y + -log Y -log (-W *(q, Or)) p(ql *, Or)} +~~~EQ 0,' P(qj a*, (11) PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 691 Date r + 1 unconditionalpaymentswill equal the paymentsto newborns,plus A timesthe unconditionaltime r payments(since only A fractionof the date r populationsurvives), plus the new additionsto unconditionalpaymentsdeterminedby the functionw'*.Equation (11) allows the deficitat r + 1 (Equation(10)) to be writtenas -log (-WO)+{{-log 7Y + 1A + (-W)dW() w IY {E -log ( w *(q, or)) P(qja*, 0)} I 1-A {EC {Y*(q, ?r+l) -q} P(q a* U, ?+ l)} (12) Since we know that (9) holds for both T' and each of its possible successors G*(Tr, OT), the first term on the right-handside of (9) (the total of non-contingent payments)must be equal betweenT' and each of its possiblesuccessors.This allows the replacementof T' in (12) with any of its possiblesuccessorsT'+ l. Reversingthe derivations from (10) to (12) derivesfor all Or -log (-W) dG(Tr+', Or)(w)} D*(G*(Tr +l, Or), O + I))={J 7 w + 1! { * y {y(q, Or+l)-q}P(qla* r+,)}=d. (13) Thus the assumptionof conditions(9) and (10) for the distribution'r imply themselves for each possible successor distribution Tr+ l. Mathematical induction then implies the constant deficit d at all dates x, r + 1, . . . regardless of the outcome of shocks (Or, or+l - .).. ). | Lemma3 impliesthat if a set of constantprices {6(0), B(0)} inducespolicieswhich satisfy(9) and (10) for any givendistributionat any givendate, this thenensuresconstant deficitsacrossall statesat all futuredates.The pricesnecessaryto inducea constantdeficit over all dates and states do not depend on the distributionT. Thus we can pick any convenient distribution and find the prices which cause constant deficits for that distribution. In particular,considerequations(9) and (12) underthe assumptionthat the distribution of utilitiesis for all generationsdegenerateat a point w0-the date zero distribution of utilities.Equation(9) becomesfor all 0 -log(W) + E (y(q, ) - q)P(ql a*, 0) = (1 - A)d. (14) Equation(12) becomesfor all 0 and any given 0 -log (-WO)+ E (y(q, ) - q)P(ql a*, 0) -log (-w'*(q, 0)) + AZQ P(qja*, 0=(I- A)d, (15) 692 REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES or, from noticing that equation (15) is simply equation (14) plus an extra term, (15) becomesfor all 0 E -log ( wP*(q,0)) P(qja*, 0)=0. (16) Note thatequation(16) impliesthat the aggregateof new unconditionalz paymentsequals zero. Further,since equation (16) is also the expectedvalue of additionalz payments givena* and the realizationof 0, (and this holds for all 0), an individual'sunconditional z paymentfollows a randomwork. Furtherstill, note that an agent's realizationof his conditionalpaymenty(q, 0) is independentand identicallydistributedover time.Thus his consumptionis the sum of a randomwalk componentand an i.i.d. componentand thus has the samepropertyof every-increasing cross-sectionalvarianceas a purerandomwalk.3 This impliesa step-by-stepmethod of constructingan equilibrium.Step 1 is to find price vectors {a(0), B(0)}, and loss-minimizing policies given these prices {a*, y*(q, 0), w'*(q,0)} such thatequation(16) holds and the aggregatedeficitis independent of the realizationof 0 or for any given 0 and all 0 # 0, E {y*(q, O)-q}P(qja*, O)=Q {y (q, 0)-q}P(qja*, 0). (17) This condition,equation (17), is a direct implicationof (14) holding for all 0. If 0 can take on n possiblevalues,equation(17) impliesn- I conditions.The conditionthat new aggregatez paymentssum to zero for all 0 (equation (16)) impliesn conditions.These are the correctnumberof conditions necessaryto pin down the 2n prices {a(0), B(0)} given the restriction that E B(0) = 1. Step 2 is to find the initialutilitypromisew0whichcausesmarketsto clearand which resultsin zero losses for the representativefirm. Since the representativefirm is the sole supplierand demanderof contingentconsumption,if pricesaresuchthatthe representative firm chooses to run a zero deficit at all dates and states (which is impliedby equations (17) and (16)) then marketsclear at all dates and states. Further,if the representative firm runs a zero deficit at all dates and states, then its losses equal zero. Thus one can find w0by simplysolving equation(14) for w0given a constantdeficitd=0. The equilibriumis then definedas price vectors (6(0), B(0)}, the loss-minimizing policies giving these prices {z*(w), a*, y*(q, 0), w'*(q,O)} and the initial utility w0constructedas above. 4. CHARACTERISTICSOF EQUILIBRIUM Comparisontofull-information framework How do consumptionprofilesdifferin this economyrelativeto its full informationcounterpart-the same economy but with observableeffort?First, with full information,it is possible there is a higher efficientlevel of effort, a*. I ignore this in this section and focus only on consumptionprofilesholdinga* constant.Consumptionprofilesgiven full informationare characterizedby full insuranceover idiosyncraticshocks. This implies y(q,, 0) =y(q2, 0) for all (q,, q2, 0) and w'(q, 0) = -1 for all q and 0. That is individual consumptionpaymentsy depend only on the aggregateshock 0 and agents start each 3. By the sequence{z,} being a randomwalk, it is meant that first differencesare i.i.d. over time and E(z,+I-z,z,) = ). PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 693 period with the same expectedutility. Individualspecificvariablessuch as q cannot be used to predictconsumptionor consumptionchanges. This is not true givenunobservedeffort.In the equilibriumpresented,an individual's consumptionat date t, c, can be expressed(wheres is the agent'sdate of birth) as Ct=y(qt, 0t)log and the first difference, ct+ - (-wo)_ t-I log (-w'(qr, Or)) (18) ct as c,+,-c,=y(q,+,O,+,)_y(t log ?(- w'(qt, Ot)).(9 Underunobservedeffort,consumptionchangesdependon individualrealizationof q, and q,+,, as well as 0, and 0,+ . This holds not only becausecontingentpaymentschange dependingon q, and q,+,, but also because of the permanentconsumptionpayment -log (-w'(q,, O,))/y. With regardto the distributionof consumption,with identicalindividualseach causing zero profitsfor the hiringfirm,full informationimpliesthat each agent consumesthe same as everyother. Consumptionvariesacrossdates only due to the aggregateshock. If one assumesthat individualsstartlife with differentP(qja, 0) functions,then it is possible to generate cross-sectionalinequalityin the full informationmodel. Nevertheless,full insuranceimpliesthat the distributionof consumptionis simplya functionof the current shock 0,. Underunobservedeffort,the distributionof consumptiondependson the entire historyof aggregateshocks (0,1... , 0,). In fact, the evolutionof consumptiondistributions is a Markovchain. Long-runproperties Given that individualconsumptionlevels have a random walk component,one would suspectthat the long-rundistributionof consumptionis degeneratesince as time goes on, the varianceof consumptionacrossa cohortincreaseswithoutlimit. However,the assumption of a constantdeath rate and overlappinggenerationsallows more reasonablelongrun properties.Overlappinggenerationsand a constantdeath rate allows the distribution of each generationto continuallyspreadwithoutcausinga degeneratelimitingdistribution of the populationas a whole. The long-runpropertiesof this economy can be characterizedas follows: First, one can note that set of continuationutilitiesan agent can have is countablesince thereare a finitenumberhe can haveat any age. The distributionof promisedutilitiesfor the economy at a point in time then is elementof the 1/(1 -A) simplexof R from the fact that the assumedpopulationsize is 1/(1 - A). This is the state of the economy.(The distributions for each generationdo not mattersince agents of all ages are identical.) One can show that if the same aggregateshock is receivedat all dates, then the distributionof utilities convergesto a non-degeneratedistribution.For an economy at least r dates old, let uPTdenote the distributionof utilitiesfor agentsweaklyyoungerthan r. (upT is an elementof theg= As-' simplexof R ', againbecausethe size of this segement of the populationequalsE As-.) If the aggregateshock is the same at all dates, then distribution TPris independent of the calandar date. The limTo mass of agents older than r becomesarbitrarilysmall. ur exists because the total 694 REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES For generalrealizationsof the sequenceof aggregateshocks,the probabilityof realizing an infinitesequenceof aggregateshockssuchthat the distributionof utilitiesconverges is zero. Young generationsconstitute a positive percentageof the population and are affectedonly by recentaggregateshocks,and thus the distributionof utilitiesis continually buffeted.If an infinitesequenceof a particularshock 0 causes a relativelytight limiting distributionof consumption,thena singlerealizationof this shockcausesthe consumption distributionto tighten. If an infinitesequenceof a differentshock 0 causes a relatively wide limitingdistributionof consumption,then a single realizationof this shock causes the consumptiondistributionto spread. Even though there is not a limitingdistributionof consumption,there is a limiting probabilitydistributionover the distributionof consumption.This is provedby proving the existenceof a limitingprobabilitydistributionover the distributionof utilities.For an economy at least r periodsold, let p' denote the probabilitymeasureover the mass of agentsweaklyyoungerthan r periodson utility point wi.4 That is if p' ([x, y]) =p, then thereis a probabilityp that the mass of agentsweaklyyoungerthan r on utilitypoint w, is in the interval[x, y]. This probabilitydoes not dependon the date sincethe distribution of utilitiesfor agents weaklyyoungerthan r periodsdependsonly on the r most recent shocks. The collectionof probabilitymeasuresp,i over all possibleutilitypoints wi definesa probabilitymeasureover the possibleutility distributionfor agentsweaklyyoungerthan r. Again, the limpO j4, exists because the total mass of agents older than r becomes arbitrarilysmall.This impliesa limitingmeasureon utilitydistributionsand thusconsumption distributions. 5. OPTIMA This section considersthe social planner'sproblemfor this economy and whether the equilibriumof the previoussection solves this problem.The first resultpresentedis that, like the representativefirm'sproblem,the socialplanner'sproblemfor this economytakes a recursiveform (Lemma4). This then allows proof that the equilibriumof the previous sectiondoes indeedsolve the socialplanner'sproblem(Lemma5). Besidesbeingof interest in and of itself, this is desirablefrom a purely practicalviewpoint since analyzingand computingoptimatends to be easierthan analyzingand computingequilibria.Statingthe socialplanner'sproblemin a formusefulfor computingequilibriumoutcomesand prices, however,requiressomewhatfurtherargument.To this end, a functionalform for the cost functionof the socialplanneris derived(Lemma6). Giventhis result,the sectionconcludes by presentinga reformulationof the social planner'sproblemsuch that the equilibrium prices fall out as functionsof the Lagrangemultiplierson the constraintsfaced by the social planner. The generalmethodologyused in this section (followingAtkeson and Lucas (1992)) is to considerthe social planneras a sort of "residualclaimant"on the resourcesof the economy. Specifically,consider the social planner as having an ability to contributea constantamountof the consumptiongood (positiveor negative)to the economyat each date and state.The socialplanner'sproblemis then to minimizethis constantcontribution to the economy (or maximizehis constantextractionfrom the economy) subjectto constraintsregardingthe ex ante utilities of the agents as well as the incentiveconditions 4. Measurepu maps the Borelsubsetsof [0, AS-'] to [0, 1]. PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 695 regardingunobservedeffort.If the representativefirm'splan from the previoussectionis not an optimal social plan, then the social plannershould be able to extracta positive constantamountfrom the economyand still give each agent the ex ante utilityhe expects firm'splanfromthe previous fromthe equilibrium.On the otherhand,if the representative section is optimal,the maximumamountthe social plannercan extract(again subjectto utility and incentiveconstraints)should be zero. It is assumedthat the plannermust treatall agentsof all generationsequally,or that each agent receivesthe same ex ante expecteddiscountedutility 1o.5In the course of proving that the equilibriumplan is optimal subjectto this constraint,it is first shown that the social planner'sproblemtakes a recursiveform wherethe state variablesof the economy are the distributionof utilities owed by the social plannerto currentlyliving agents, and (implicitly)the ex ante utility owed by the plannerto agents born in future periods, i0. To this end, let B be the set of Borel-measurabledistributionswith total measure 1/(1 -A), the size of the populationof living agents at any time, and let TPeB representa distributionof continuationexpecteddiscountedutilitiesfor currentlyliving agents. Define X*(T): B-.R as the minimumconstant contributionby the social planner which allows the provisionthroughan incentivecompatibleplan of P to currentlyliving agents and the deliveryof voto agents born in futureperiods. I definean efficientplan (or an optimum) as a specificationof contingentconsumptionand recommendedeffort levelsthat achievesa givendistributionof utilities' with the minimumconstantcontribution by the social planner,X*(T ).6 The claim that the social planner'sproblemis recursiveis essentiallythat the cost functionX*(T) can be stated as a function of itself in a Bellman-typeequation.Given this, the distributionof promisedutilitiesto currentlylivingagents' completelysummarizes history,allowingthe plannerto choose one-periodplans conditionalon this distribution and a rule to generatenew promisedutilities. In this recursiveformulation,for a given distributionT, let the choice variablesfor the social plannerbe the same as for firms,except now let each of the functionsdepend explicitlyon w. That is, the social plannerchooses functionsz(w), a(w), y(w, q, 0), and firm'sproblem,let z(w) representan unconditional w'(w, q, 0). As with the representative paymentand let promisedfutureutilitiesequalexp (-yz)w'(w, q, 0). (Again, z can always be set to zero.) The following Lemma proves that X*(T) indeed solves a Bellman-typeequation. Essentially,this Lemma argues that the minimumconstant contributionnecessaryto support a plan [z(w), a(w), y(w, q, 0), w'(w, q, 0)] is the maximum of the contribution necessarytoday for each possible 0 realization,and the constantcontributionnecessary to support each of the possible utility distributionsfor tomorrow.Again, let G(UT,0) denote the date r + 1 distributionof utilities if the date r distributionis T and shock 0 occurs, given the policies z(w) and w'(w,q, 0) for generating the r + 1 utility distribution. 5. Thisassumptionthrowsout all trueoptimaif all of themhavethe propertythat generationsaretreated unequally.Thatis, with overlappinggenerationsit mightbe possiblethroughintergenerational transfersto raise the utilityof latergenerationswithoutloweringthe utilityof earliergenerations.Sincethis modelhas an initial date t = 0, discounting,and equalsize generations(afterthe first),I believeI have ruledout such schemes. 6. Atkesonand Lucas(1992)definethe cost of a givenpolicyas the supremum overdatesof the necessary gift, and the true cost of a distributionas the infimumof the cost of all possiblepolicies.Thus they do not assumethat any cost can actuallybe attained,only arbitrarilycloselyattained.Thisdid not substantiallychange theirresults,so here I simplyassumefor conveniencethat all maximaare attained. REVIEWOF ECONOMICSTUDIES 696 Lemma 4. as follows: The costfunction X*(T) is afixedpoint of thefollowing operator Tdefined CTX)(T)= max max sX(G(T, 0)), min z(w),a(w),y(w,q,0),w'(w,q,0) 0 EC {z(w) +y(w, q, 0) - q}P(qja(w), 0)dT(w), X(G(T, 0))} x (20) w subject to thepromise-keepingconstraintsimpliedby (1) and the incentive constraints implied by (2) holdingfor we W. Proof. The proof is nearly identical to the proof in Atkeson and Lucas (1992), Lemma4.1, and is in the Appendix. 11 An optimum can be defined as the policies [z(wjT), a(wj'P), y(w, q, OJT),w'(w,q, 0JT)] whichsolve (20) subjectto (1) and (2) for all possibledistributions T, and an initial utility vo such that X(Wo)= 0, where'P0is the distributionwhere all mass lies at the point vo. This result now allows the proof that equilibriumof the previoussectionsis indeedan optimum. Lemma 5. The equilibriumpolicies of the representativefirm [z*(w) = -log (-w)/ y, a*, y*(q, 0), w'*(q, 0)], together with the equilibriuminitial promised utility wo, are an optimum. Proof. The proof argues first that the representativefirm'spolicies are a feasible solutionto the socialplanner'sproblemand implya cost X*(Wo)= 0 for the socialplanner. If these policiesare not an optimumthen theremust exist anotherset of feasiblepolicies which allow the social plannerto extracta constantpositiveamount from the economy. This is shown to contradictthe assumedcost minimizationby the representativefirm.A more detailedargumentis in the appendix. 11 At this point, the Bellman equation (20) is not in a particularlyuseful form for calculatingor analyzingequilibriaby findingoptima.The followingLemmasolvesfor the social planner'scost functionX* up to constant. Lemma 6. Thefunction X* takes the form X(T) - log (-w) dT(w) +K, (21) where K= min {Q {y(q, O)-q}P(q a, 0)), (22) a,y(q,O),w'(q,O) for any particular 0e0 and where the minimization is subject to the incentive condition (4), the promise keeping condition (5), the constant payments conditionsfor all 0e0, (16), and the constant current deficit condition, equation (17) for all 0$0. Proof. See Appendix. 11 PHELAN INCENTIVESAND AGGREGATESHOCKS 697 The formationallows us, with one qualification,to find the marketclearingprices usingthe Lagrangemultipliersassociatedwith the constantdeficitconstraints (17) (to get B(0)) and the constant paymentsconstraint(16) (to get the 6(0)). The qualificationis that the constraintset for the minimizationproblemin (22) mustbe convex and thus we.can invoke the Kuhn-Tuckertheorem.One way to avoid convexityproblems is to formulatethe choiceproblemin termsof lotteriesas in Phelanand Townsend(1991). This is avoidedhere solely for ease of exposition. The Kuhn-Tuckertheoremallows us to state that thereexist multiplierslo for 0$ 0 and po for each 0e0 such that the optimalpolicies [a*,y*(q, 0), w'*(q, 0)] solve {a(0), B(0)} min {Q {y(q, C)-q}P(qla, 0)) +Eo, {(A Q {y(q, 0) -q}P(qla, {y(q, 0)-q}P(qja, +ZQ a,y(q,6),w'(q,6) -(Q 0))) {ZQ 0)) -log (-w'(q, 0)) P(qla, 0)} (23) subject to the incentivecondition (4) and the promise keeping condition (5), and, in addition,that each of the marketclearingconstraints(equations(17) and (16)) holds for all 0. This Lagrangianis a particularlyusefulform of the social planner'sproblem.In this form, the planner'sproblemhas the same constraintset as the firm'sproblem.Further, the objectivefunctionsin the two problemsdifferonly in the coefficientson the moments EQ {y(q, 0) -q}P(qla, 0) and EQ Pog(-w(q0))P(qla, 0). (24) Thus to give the firm the same objectivefunction as the planner,one simply needs to choose pricesto equatethe coefficientson thesemomentsor (fromequations(7) and (23)) for 0, B(O) = I-E00 AO, for #0 , B(0)= AO, and for all 0, ()A - 1 SA p. (25) Since a =Eo B(0)3(0), the 6(0) are impliedby the system of equationsdefinedby the last expressionin (25) for all 0e0.7 This derivationallowsus to easilyfindmarketclearingpricesby solvingthis planner's problem.Further,the convexityassumptioncan be checkedex post. That is, if one derives a solution to the optimum problem allowing for probabilisticchoice, but the optimal policies are neverthelessdeterministicin the form above, then any non-convexityin the constraintset given deterministicchoice is harmlessand one can then use the above rules to deriveprices {B(0), 3(0)). 6. CONCLUSION The purposeof this paperwas to createa tractableframeworkto makepredictionsregarding the dynamicsof consumptionand distributionsof consumption.Of course,it is possible to think of other ways of generatinga non-trivialdistributiontheory. One would be to simplyclose marketsover state-contingentconsumption(or insurancemarkets),but allow tradingover dates (or creditmarkets).This would not necessarilybe easierto solve since one would still face the problemthat withoutspecialassumptions,interestrateswill be a 7. If the 9 is broughtto the right-handside by multiplyingeachside of the expressionin (25) by (I - 9A) then the expressionis linearin the 3(0) and thus the systemhas a uniquesolution. 698 REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES functionof the distributionof wealth. Further,normativeanalysiswould be hinderedby the fact that one has left unexplainedwhy it is that insuranceis hindered. In this model, limitedinsurancecomes directlyfrom the informationalassumptions of the model.Giventhese,the equilibriumis efficient.The equilibriumheremost likelyhas differentconsumptionseriesimplicationsthan those impliedby simplyclosing insurance markets. The best insurance possible given information constraint-the equilibrium presentedhere-is not only more insurancethanwould exist givenclosedinsurancemarkets, but should also be expectedto look differentin regardto how consumptionmoves with aggregateshocks. The creationof models with specificdifferingpredictionsallows these differencesto be evaluatedin relationto data. APPENDIX Proofof Lemma4. Again, let X*(T) be the trueminimumconstantgift whichallowsthe attainmentof the distributionof utilities P and for the deliveryof utility voto agentsborn in futureperiods.The Lemma statesthat T(X*)=X*. First I show that T(X*)>X*. Suppose that for some T, (TX*)(T) <X*(T). This implies that there exist functions [z?(w), ao(w), yo(w, q, 0), w'?(w, q, 0)J such that X*(T) > max max {J 2 Q {z0(w) +y?(w, q, O)- q}P(qla0(w), O)dT(w), X*(GO(TP, ))} (26) whereG?(Q,0) is the distributionof utilitiesgeneratedby [z?(w),w'0(w)lgivenshock 0. Let the possibly time-dependent plan [z,(w), a,(w), y,(w, q, 0), w'(w, q, 0)1,=O., denote the policy that actuallyachievesX*(P). Definea new time-dependentplan [z,(w), ao(w), y,?(w,q, 0), w',(w, q, 0)1,=O.,, by followingplan [z?,ao,yo, w'0lat the firstdate and plan [z, a', y, w' I for each date thereafter.This is a feasible planthatactuallydeliversthe requiredutilities,anddoes so at a cost (TX*)(T) <X*(T) whichis a contradiction. Thus, (TX*)(TP) X*(TP). Now suppose for some P that X*(T) <(TX*)(T). Let [z,?(w),ao(w), yo(w, q, 0), w',(w, q, 0)1,=O,., denote the policy that actuallyachievesX*(TQ).The firstdate of this plan, [zo,ao,yo, w'/o,satisfiesthe incentiveconstraints and promise keeping constraintsfor the recursiveformulation.Further,its date-zerodeficit must be weakly less than X*(TQ) given distribution P and any 0. Further, since [z?,(w), ao(w), y,(w, q, 0), w',(w, q, O)1,=O.<,has a deficit weakly less than X*(TQ)in every period, the cost of each of its possible successorsunder[zoo,w'ol,G0(T, 0), must be weaklyless thanX*(T). This impliesthat max max {z?(w)+y?(w,q, O)-q}P(qla?(w), {jE'Q O)dT(w),X*(GO(T, O))} X*(T)<(TX*)(T). (27) Since[zoo, is a feasiblerecursiveplan, this contradictsthe minimizationin the definitionof T. Thus, ao,yo, w'OJ (TX*)(TP)5X*(TP). II Proof of Lemma5. Considerthe solution to the firm'sproblem.Therez*(w)= -log (-w)/y, and the policies[a*,y*(q, 0), w'*(q,0)] solvedthe minimizationproblemin (7) subjectto (5) and (4). This impliesthat the combination[z*(w),a*, y*(q, 0), w'*(q,0)1 satisfies(2) and (1), or that the solution to the equilibrium problemis a feasiblesolutionto the optimumproblem.The plansofferedby the firmare incentivecompatible and give each agent his requiredex-anteutility. Further,recallthat the solutionto the equilibriumproblemdeliverszero aggregatedeficitsat all datesand firmfaces on the firstcalendardate (all states.Let TObe the distributionof utilitypromisesthe representative mass on wo).Since the firm'splan is a feasibleplan for the social planner,the plannercan at least achievea firm'splan maximumdeficitover all datesand statesof zero, or X*(To):0. This impliesthat the representative is not optimalonly if thereis anotherplan whichallows a negativeconstantpayment,or that X(TO)< 0. Now suppose exactly that. This implies there exists a solution to (20) (say [z(wl1), al(wl'), P(w,q, 01J), W'(w,q, 01T)Jwhichdeliversstrictlynegativedeficitsfor all datesand states.Couldthis planhave been implementedby the representivefirm?Since I assumed(and confirmed)that the prices{6(0), B(0)} did firmdid not conditionpolicieson T. Nevertheless,I did not dependon the distributionT, the representative firmto choose policiesindependentof T. It was simplynot in its interestto do not constrainthe representative INCENTIVES AND AGGREGATE SHOCKS PHELAN 699 firmoptimallychoosespolicieswhichare independentof w, again,this so. Further,althoughthe representative was not arbitrarilyimposed,but derivedfrom the choice problem.Thus the representativefirm could have chosento implement[A(wlIT), a(wlT), P(w,q, 01IT),w'(w,q, 01IT)J. Further,if thesepoliciesproducenegativedeficitsat everydateand everystate,thenif at leastone element of {6(0), B(O)} is positiveand all othersare non-negative(a conditionwhichcan be checkedfor any candidate firm.Thiscontradictsthe optimalequilibrium)thenthispolicywillproducepositiveprofitsfor the representative firm.This contradictionimplies ity of [z*(w),a*, y*(q, 0), w'*(q, 0)1 from the perspectiveof the representative that the equilibriumconstructedin the previoussectionis optimalgiventhat it has non-negativepricesand at least one positive price.8 11 Proof of Lemma 6. As in the proof of Lemma1, I exploita boundingfunctionof X* whichtakes the form of (21). Let X(T) with constantK denotethe cost functionassociatedwith the removalof the incentive conditions. Imposingrestrictionson the minimizationproblemdefiningT (equation20) that z(w)= -log (-w)/y and that policiesdo not dependon w or T definesa new operatorT(X). ApplyingT to a functionof the formin (21) implies - ~X)('P) -log (-w) dP(w) + - W min maxmax -A 1 -log (-w'(q, 1_ G (a.y(q.0).w'(q.0)) Y E (y(q, 0 - q)P(qla, 0), A )) P(qla, 0) + (28) subjectto the promisekeepingconstraints(5) and incentiveconstraints(4) fromthe firm'sproblem.If the true cost functionX* is of the formin (21) it must be a fixedpoint of P as well as T fromLemma5. Equation(28) also showsthat the operatorT preservesthe guessedform (21), sincethe solutionto the minimizationproblem does not dependon the distributionT. Continuingin this line, one can imposecondition(16), that new-contingentpaymentsw'(q, 0) integrate to zero for all 0. Again, this impliesa new operator(say T) for whichX* must again be a fixedpoint if it is of the formin (21). This impliesthat (28) becomes ~~C (TX)('P)iJ ~-log(-w) W dT'(w)+ minmax max {Q(y(q, ~~~~~(a.,y(q,0),w'(q,0)) Y 0)- q)P(qla, 0), K}, (29) 0 subjectto the promisekeepingconstraints(5), the incentiveconstraints(4), and condition(16). This makes transparentthat for functionsof the formin (21), operatorT is non-decreasingin the constanttermK. Now considerXi = T(X), or applyingoperatorT to the cost functiongivenno incentiveconstaints(which is of the guessedform(21) withconstanttermK). SinceT(X) mustbe weaklygreaterthanX fromthe incentive constraintsin the minimizationproblemdefiningT, one can discardthe secondpart of the innermaximization and write (TX)(v)f w -log (-w) dT(w)+ 7 min maxE (y(q, 0)-q)P(qla, (a.y(q6 )) 0), (30) 1 where,again,the minimizationis subjectto conditions(5), (4), and (16). Let K, be the constanttermassociated withXi, equalto the minimizationin (30). Substitutingthis definitionfor K, into (29) impliesthatXI is a fixed point of T. At this point, it is clear that the true cost functionX* is a fixed point of T if it is of the guessedform (21). The proof continuesby showingthat all fixedpoints of T otherthan Xi cannotbe the truecost function and thus eitherXI=X*, or X* is not of the guess form.Furtherexaminationof (29) showsthat everyfunction of the formin (21) with K> K, but less thanor equalto the upperboundis also a fixedpoint of T. Nevertheless, sincethe policiesassociatedwith XI actuallydo achieveany distributionof utilitiesP with a constantgift less than or equalto X,(T), only XI (the minimumof this set of fixed-pointcost functions)can be a candidatefor 8. Some readershavecommentedthat this resultis surprisinglyeasy to provegiventhe usualdifficultyof provingthe FirstWelfareTheoremin infinite-goodsettings,especiallywithoverlappinggenerations.Whatmakes this proof easy is that 1) the firmslive in everydate, and 2) that an optimumhere is definedvery differently than usual. Here for one allocationto constitutean improvementover anotherallocation,it must use fewer resourcesat every date and state. The specialcases that cause problemsin the usual First WelfareTheorem proofswill probablycause the dualityapproachto breakdown here. REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES 700 the truecost functionX* amongthe class of functionsof the form of (21). The functionXI is an upperbound of the truecost function. Thereare possiblyotherfixedpointsof T not of the formof (21). LetX be sucha fixedpoint. If for some T,X(T) >X1(T), then X(T) cannot be the true cost function.Again, sinceX,(T) is an upperbound on the true cost, any functionthat is anywheregreaterthan XI cannot be the true cost function.Lastly, since T is for all P this implies (TX2)(T) ?(TX3)(T) monotonic (if X2(T) <X3(T) for all T), it is not possible that for all T, X(TP) <XI(TP). The statements(T(X)=X), (T(X1) =XI), and (for all T, XI(T') iX(TP))togetherviolate monotonicity.Thusif thereareany fixedpointsof T not of the formin (21), they arenot the truecost function. Thus X*=X,. Giventhat we have derivedX* as T(X), the finalstep is to reconcilethe expressionfor the constantterm in equation(30) with the constantterm in the statementof the Lemma.SinceX* is the true cost function, imposinga constraintthat the currentperioddeficitbe constantacross0 is harmlessbecausethis a characteristic This allowsus to specifythe socialplanner'sproblemas one of minimizing of theconstructedmarketequilibrium. the deficitgiven a specific0 realization,say 0, subjectto the constraintthat the deficitgiven other 0 values equalsthis amount.Using equation(30) this implies = X*(T) X -log (-w) dT(w) + min {Q {y(q, O)- q}P(qla, O)}, (31) a.y(q0).w'(q6) wherethe minimizationis subjectto the incentivecondition(4), the promisekeepingcondition(5), the constant paymentsconditionsfor all OeO, (16), and the constantcurrentdeficitcondition,equation(17) for all 0 #0. 11 Acknowledgements.Formerly,"Incentives,Inequality,and the BusinessCycle".The authorwould like to thankAndrewAtkeson,John Cochrane,Robert Lucas,Lars Ljungqvist,Pete Streufert,LarrySamuelson, RobertTownsendand participantsat seminarsat the Universityof Wisconsin,the FederalReserveBank of Minneapolis,and the February1992 NBER EconomicFluctuationsMeetingsin Palo Alto, California.The authorreceivedfinancialsupportfromNational ScienceFoundationgrantSES-9111-926. REFERENCES ATKESON,A. and LUCAS,R. (1992), "OnEfficientDistributionwith PrivateInformation",Reviewof Economic Studies, 59, 427-453. BANERJEE,A. and NEWMAN, A. (1991), "Risk-Bearingand the Theoryof IncomeDistribution",Review of Economic Studies, 58, 211-236. COCHRANE,J. (1991), "A SimpleTest of ConsumptionInsurance",Journalof PoliticalEconomy,99, 957976. GREEN,E. (1987),"Lendingand the Smoothingof UninsurableIncome",in E. Prescottand N. Wallace(eds.), Contractual Arrangementsfor Intertemporal Trade (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press). HANSEN, G. (1985), "IndivisibleLabor and the BusinessCycle",Journalof MonetaryEconomics,16, 309327. MACE, B. (1991), "Full InsuranceIn the Presenceof AggregateUncertainty",Journalof PoliticalEconomy, 99, 928-956. PHELAN, C. (1994), "Incentives,Insurance,and the Variabilityof Consumptionand Leisure",Journalof Economic Dynamics and Control, 18, 581-600. Optima", PHELAN, C. and TOWNSEND,R. (1991), "ComputingMulti-period,Information-Constrained Review of Economic Studies, 58, 853-882. PRESCOTT,E. and TOWNSEND,R. (1984), "ParetoOptimaand CompetitiveEquilibriawith AdverseSelection and MoralHazard",Econometrica, 52, 21-46. Journalof MonetaryEconomics,21, ROGERSON,R. (1988), "IndivisibleLabor,Lotteriesand Equilibrium", 3-16. SPEAR,S. and SRIVASTAVA,S. (1987),"OnRepeatedMoralHazardwithDiscounting",Reviewof Economic Studies, 54, 599-618. TAUB,B. (1990),"AggregateFluctuations,InterestRates,and RepeatedInsuranceunderPrivateInformation", (manuscript,Universityof Illinois). THOMAS,J. and WORRALL,T. (1990), "IncomeFluctuationsand AsymmetricInformation:An Example of a RepeatedPrincipal-AgentProblem",Journalof EconomicTheory,51, 367-390. 62, 539-592. TOWNSEND,R. M (1994), "Riskand Insurancein VillageIndia",Econometrica,
© Copyright 2024