What is Transnational Counter-Terrorism Law-Making? Tilmann Altwicker PLEASE NOTE: THIS IS A DRAFT ONLY. PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE WITHOUT PERMISSION OF THE AUTHOR. Abstract ........................................................................................................................................................ 2 Introduction................................................................................................................................................. 2 A. Transnational Counter-Terrorism Law and Non-State Actors ................................................ 7 I. Regulatory Law............................................................................................................................... 8 II. Depth and Direct Effect ............................................................................................................... 12 III. B. Constitutional Gatekeeping .................................................................................................... 20 Reasons for Transnational Cooperation on Counter-Terrorism ................................................ 26 I. Efficiency Gains ............................................................................................................................ 27 II. External Effects ............................................................................................................................. 28 III. C. Weakest Link Public Good ...................................................................................................... 29 Techniques of Transnational Law-Making on Counter-Terrorism ........................................... 30 I. Harmonization .............................................................................................................................. 31 II. Imposition ...................................................................................................................................... 36 III. Diffusion .................................................................................................................................... 39 Conclusion: Two Principles of Transnational Counter-Terrorism Law-Making ............................ 42 Dr. iur. Tilmann Altwicker, LL.M. (CEU). Lecturer at the University of Basle. Email: tilmann.altwicker@unibas.ch. I thank Anne Peters and Nuscha Wieczorek for comments on an earlier version. The usual disclaimer applies. Abstract The paper examines international law-making on counter-terrorism. After more than 50 years of suppression conventions on counter-terrorism, intense preoccupation by the Security Council with issues of counter-terrorism in the last decade and a vast array of soft law instruments it is time for stocktaking of structural principles underlying global counter-terrorism law-making. The core of my argument is that global counter-terrorism law exists in large part as ‘transnational law’ and that it differs from (traditional) international law both regarding the quality of the norms as well as regarding the techniques used for its creation. These differences can (at least partly) be explained by a socio-legal analysis of the reasons behind international cooperation in this field. ‘Transnational law’ refers to law on the conduct of individuals with cross-border application or effect. Global counter-terrorism law is a prime example of the emerging field of transnational law. The paper addresses transnational counter-terrorism law both from a doctrinal as well as from a socio-legal perspective. On a doctrinal level, some key features of transnational counter-terrorism law are analyzed (e.g. its regulatory nature and its potential for direct effect). The socio-legal analysis sheds light upon the reasons why and how transnational counter-terrorism law is created. The paper concludes that there are two (main) structural principles of transnational law-making on counter-terrorism: the principle of integration and the principle of integrity. The ‘principle of integration’ contends that the gap between ‘the international’ and ‘the domestic’ in counter-terrorism is increasingly bridged through an innovative body of law. This is evidenced, e.g., by global counter-terrorism law taking the role of a ‘model law’ for domestic law-making, often facilitated by soft law guidance on how to ‘domesticize’ universal norms on counter-terrorism. The ‘principle of integrity’ requires global counterterrorism law-making to be informed and constrained by concerns of transnational constitutionalism. Introduction Counter-terrorism has become a highly innovative field of international law-making.1 For more than a decade now (though with origins long before the attacks of 9/11), the international legal While there is still no universal definition of terrorism in international law, other disciplines such as international relations and philosophy have come up with viable working definitions. In this paper, I follow the definition given by Todd Sandler defining terrorism as “the premeditated use or threat of use of violence by individuals or subnational groups to obtain a political or social objective through intimidation of a large audience beyond that of the immediate victims”, Todd Sandler, ‘Collective versus Unilateral Responses to Terrorism’ (2005) 124 Public Choice 75. 1 2 agenda has been preoccupied with counter-terrorism.2 The universal legislative framework against terrorism currently consists of 14 multilateral conventions,3 two law-making Security Council resolutions4 as well as a number of influential soft law instruments.5 A closer look at this universal legislative framework reveals that international law-making is in a process of change. Though it seems too early to say whether the innovations in the field of counter-terrorism are here to stay and may even spill over to other fields of international law (disregarding for the moment whether that would be desirable at all),6 a systematic account of the principles of global counter-terrorism law-making is lacking.7 While a comprehensive account would have to include both the domestic dimension of global counter-terrorism lawmaking as well as judicial responses to it, a more limited approach is pursued here. The research question that this paper seeks to answer is this: What is transnational counter-terrorism lawmaking? To answer this requires an argument on the existence of transnational law (and what distinguishes it from international law), why and how it is created, and what principles its creation follows. For an overview see Nigel D. White, ‘The United Nations and Counter-Terrorism’, in Ana María Salinas de Frías, Katja LH Samuel and Nigel D White (eds), Counter-Terrorism: International Law and Practice (OUP, Oxford, 2012) 54. 3 The UN Treaty Collection Database lists 14 major conventions (and their amendments) on the topic of terrorism, see <https://treaties.un.org/Pages/DB.aspx?path=DB/studies/page2_en.xml&menu=MTDSG> accessed 19 May 2014. For a general overview see Alex Conte, Human Rights in the Prevention and Punishment of Terrorism (Springer 2010), ch 3. Regarding treaty-law, I limit my analysis to the following five conventions deposited with the UN SecretaryGeneral: Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons, including Diplomatic Agents (the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons) (New York, 14 December 1973, 1035 UNTS 167); International Convention against the Taking of Hostages (the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages) (New York, 18 December 1979, 1316 UNTS 205); International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings (the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings) (New York, 12 January 1998, 2149 UNTS 256); International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism (the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism) (New York, 10 January 2000, 2178 UNTS 197); International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism (the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism) (New York, 14 September 2005, 2445 UNTS 89). 4 SC Res. 1373 (2001); SC Res. 1540 (2004). 5 For reasons of space, I limit the analysis to the FATF Special Recommendations on Terrorist Financing, October 2001 (rev. 2012) <http://www.fatf-gafi.org/topics/fatfrecommendations/documents/ixspecialrecommendations.html> accessed 13 May 2014. Other influential soft law instruments are the General Assembly’s Global Counter-Terrorism Strategy, GA Res. 60/288, 20 September 2006, and Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms while Countering Terrorism, GA Res. 65/221, 5 April 2011. 6 For a critical stance see Kim Lane Scheppele, ‘From a War on Terrorism to Global Security Law’ < http://www.ias.edu/about/publications/ias-letter/articles/2013-fall/scheppele-terrorism> accessed 16 May 2014. 7 The term ‘principle’ refers to a highly ambiguous, context-sensitive yet indispensible concept of legal research. In the present context, I use of the concept of ‘principle’ (unless explicitly stated otherwise) in terms of a ‘structural principle’ denoting order in an otherwise under-organized set of legal materials and thus rationalizing it. ‘Structural principles’ are “scholarly abstractions which define legal structures within the positive law in the sense of significant regularities”, Armin von Bogdandy, ‘General Principles of International Public Authority: Sketching a Research Field’ (2008) 9 German LJ 1909, 1910. 2 3 There are four preliminary remarks. First, it should be noted that the present analysis is concerned with the ‘legislative’ part of global counter-terrorism law-making, i.e. the creation of norms of an abstract-general nature.8 The paper does not have much to say about concreteindividual law-making, e.g. in the form of ‘targeted sanctions’ by the Security Council or about international case-law on enforcement measures of global counter-terrorism. Second, in order to be able to answer the research question one must have an idea of what international law is fundamentally about, what interests it serves (and how). To phrase it as a question: What assumption concerning the purpose of international law do we make when we say that (more) international law is desirable or even necessary in the fight against global terrorism? For the aims of this paper, I assume that international law is in essence about cooperation among the actors of international law.9 For support, I rely on a recent work by Joel Trachtman, The Future of International Law.10 I follow Trachtman (who, in turn, relies on Wolfgang Friedmann) on his starting point that international law is about (a formal type of) cooperation.11 Third, one needs to define ‘transnational law’ in order to find out the principles underlying its creation. There have been many definitional attempts, but more often than not they do not offer a promising avenue for further legal research.12 Throughout this paper, I will refer to For a conceptual overview see Jutta Brunnée, ‘International Legislation’ (Max Planck Encyclopedia of Public International Law, MEPIL, October 2010) < http://opil.ouplaw.com/home/epil> accessed 19 May 2014. 9 In this paper, I do not explicitly justify this assumption. However, I submit that it can legitimately claim plausibility: Speaking of international law as a formal type of cooperation contains, in my view, a considerably weak and widely shared assumption about the finality of international law (far weaker than, e.g., contending that international law is about ‘peace’ or about a ‘just world order’). 10 Joel P. Trachtman, The Future of International Law: Global Government (CUP 2013). The following is based on my review of Trachtman’s work, see Tilmann Altwicker, ‘Die Zukunft des Völkerrechts – Rechtsökonomisch betrachtet’ (2014) Zeitschrift für Rechtswissenschaftliche Forschung 115. 11 Trachtman (n 10), ch. 2. 12 Definitions of transnational law are often either too broad or too narrow. Philip Jessup famously defined ‘transnational law’ in his 1956 Storrs Lectures as “all law which regulates actions or events that transcend national frontiers … [relating to] [b]oth public and private international law … [as well as] other rules which do not wholly fit into such standard categories”, Philip C. Jessup, Transnational Law (Yale University Press 1956) 2. Despite its prima facie broadness, Jessup’s definition is too restricted to capture what is crucial in the study of transnational law: Jessup’s definition does not seem to cover ‘transnational issues’, Craig Scott, “Transnational Law” as Proto-Concept: Three Conceptions’ (2009) 10 German LJ 859, 864 (stating that “transnational issues” are those that are “constructed by interacting normative … discourses”, rather than “physical” cross-border actions or effects). Most definitions of transnational law are too broad, however. Hathaway asserts that “transnational law includes all law that has crossborders effect, whereas international law refers only to treaties or other law that governs interactions between states”, Oona Hathaway, ‘Between Power and Principle: An Integrated Theory of International Law’ (2005) 72 Univ of Chic LR 469, 473 note 11. Vicki Jackson states that “[t]he term ‘transnational’ encompasses not only international law as it is traditionally understood (to embrace widely adhered to treaties, conventions, and customary international law), but 8 4 ‘transnational law’ as ‘law on the conduct of individuals with cross-border application or effect’.13 Transnational law, thus, has two conceptual elements: One element pertains to the cross-border application or effect of norms, and the other to the conduct of individuals as the object or target of these norms. On the basis of this definition, large parts of international law dealing with inter-state affairs (e.g. the rules on state responsibility, the law of diplomatic relations) would not be considered as ‘transnational law’.14 International human rights, on the other hand, establishing entitlements for individuals in a multiplicity of states, are ‘transnational law’. By using this doctrinal concept of transnational law we are able to flag out some norms (of international or domestic law) as belonging to ‘transnational law’. Fourth, regarding method, how should one analyze transnational law (and, as part of that, transnational counter-terrorism law) and the principles underlying its creation? An analysis of transnational law on counter-terrorism has to be ‘doctrinal’, i.e. systemizing a bundle of norms and interpreting them on the basis of principles, as well as stating potential legal problems. For an inquiry on the principles underlying the creation of transnational counter-terrorism law I suggest using ‘socio-legal analysis’ (explaining the interaction of a variety of actors in the creation of a distinct body of law).15 A socio-legal analysis of transnational law seems rewarding for a number of reasons: First, one of the benefits is that socio-legal analysis allows for the critique (and, maybe ultimately demanding the dissolution) of exceedingly problematic also regional agreements and bilateral agreements, as well as the domestic law of foreign nations when considered, relied on, or distinguished in another tribunal’s or law-making body’s decisions. Transnational law may also include the domestic law of particular countries that seek to regulate transnational phenomena, such as migration, ‘trafficking,’ or citizenship”, ea, Constitutional Engagement in a Transnational Era (OUP 2010) 286 note 7. 13 This definition is inspired by the one given by Daniel Bethlehem, ‘The End of Geography: The Changing Nature of the International System and the Challenge to International Law’ (2014) 25 EJIL 9, 23 (“the law that applies internationally to the conduct of individuals”). See, similarly, Gregory Shaffer, ‘Transnational Legal Process and State Change’ (2012) 37 Law & Social Inquiry 229, 232 (defining “transnational norms” as “legal norms that apply across borders to parties located in more than one jurisdiction”). 14 As to the relationship between the concepts of ‘transnational’ and ‘international law’ it should be noted that they are only partially overlapping: Some, but not all, international law is ‘transnational’ (maybe then best characterized as international law in a ‘transnational mode’). At the same time, ‘transnational law’ is not necessarily ‘international law’ on a formal account of its source. Instead, also ‘domestic law’ can be ‘transnational law’. See Anne-Marie Slaughter who states, “[t]ransnational law has many definitions. I mean to include here simply national law that is designed to reach actors beyond national borders: the assertion of extraterritorial jurisdiction. Extraterritorial jurisdictional provisions are often the first effort a national government is inclined to make to regulate activity outside its borders with substantial effects within its borders”, Anne-Marie Slaughter, ‘A Liberal Theory of International Law’ (2000) 94 Am Soc’y of Int’l L Proc 240. 15 My distinction of ‘doctrinal’ and ‘socio-legal’ analysis of law differs from the conceptual differentiation suggested by Ronald Dworkin, ‘Hart and the Concepts of Law’ (2006) 119 Harv L Rev F 95, 97‒8 (according to whom a sociological concept relates to the question “what makes a particular structure of governance a legal system rather than some other form of social control, such as morality, religion, force, or terror?” and the doctrinal to the problem of “what makes a statement of what the law of some jurisdiction requires or permits true”). 5 doctrinal dichotomies such as ‘law/non-law’, ‘public/private’, and ‘state/non-state’.16 In the context of global counter-terrorism law, e.g., we face influential ‘soft law’ (such as the FATF Special Recommendations) that in some ways defies the traditional ‘law/non-law’-dichotomy. Second, in departing from a rigid, formalistic approach to legal sources and form, law in the transnational sphere becomes a functional concept.17 In this perspective, exciting questions arise concerning a functional division of (multilevel) law-making competences, e.g. ‘On what level should a particular counter-terrorism problem be regulated?’, or ‘What function should domestic counter-terrorism law assume from a transnational law-perspective?’18 Third, a sociolegal perspective on transnational law allows us to develop a more – in my view – adequate understanding of how global law is made by interaction of a variety of actors through more advanced sociological descriptions of law-making: for example by allowing – instead of binary, ‘all or nothing’-solutions – continuum, ‘more or less’-solutions,19 or by using cyclical explanations of global law-making20. The paper has three parts. Part A contains a doctrinal analysis of transnational counter-terrorism law. It is about the existence of such a thing as ‘transnational counter-terrorism law’, and about the main legal problems (direct effect, ‘constitutional gatekeeping’) that ensue from it. Part B outlines three reasons why states cooperate on issues of global counter-terrorism. Part C analyzes three techniques used for transnational counter-terrorism law-making. These parts utilize a socio-legal approach to transnational law and explain why and how actors create transnational counter-terrorism law. The conclusion, then, sums up the discussion through the perspective of two structural principles underlying universal law-making on counter-terrorism: The ‘principle of integration’ contends that the gap between ‘the international’ and ‘the Ralf Michaels, ‘Globalization and Law: Law Beyond the State’ in Reza Banaka and Max Travers (eds), Law and Social Theory (Hart 2013) 287. See also Peer Zumbansen, ‘Transnational Law’ in Jan Smits (ed), Encyclopedia of Comparative Law (Edward Elgar Publishing 2006) 738 (“This framework would help to reflect on the dichotomies underlying and informing international law while decisively moving onward to embrace a wider and more adequate view of global human activities”). 17 Michaels (n 16) 287. 18 For a possible theoretical basis of a functional division of regulatory competences see Jürgen Habermas, ‘A Political Constitution for the Pluralist World Society?’ (2007) 34 J of Chinese Phil 331; id, ‘The Constitutionalization of International Law and the Legitimation Problems of a Constitution for World Society’ (2008) 15 Constellations 444. For lack of space, the questions surrounding a functional division of (multilevel) law-making cannot be addressed here. 19 See Dinah Shelton, International Law and Relative Normativity” in Malcolm Evans (ed), International Law (OUP 2003) 145, 167. I am grateful to Anne Peters for drawing my attention to this point. 20 See Terence C. Halliday and Bruce G. Carruthers, ‘The Recursivity of Law: Global Norm Making and National Lawmaking in the Globalization of Corporate Insolvency Regimes’ (2007) 112 Am J of Sociology 1135; Terence C. Halliday, ‘Recursivity of Global Normmaking: A Sociolegal Agenda’ (2009) 5 Annu Rev L aw Soc Sci 263. 16 6 domestic’ in counter-terrorism is increasingly bridged through an innovative body of law. The ‘principle of integrity’ requires global counter-terrorism law-making to be informed and constrained by concerns of transnational constitutionalism. A. Transnational Counter-Terrorism Law and Non-State Actors Is there something like ‘transnational counter-terrorism law’? The first part provides a doctrinal analysis of what I would call ‘transnational counter-terrorism law’.21 As stated in the Introduction, transnational law refers to norms on the conduct of individuals with cross-border application or effect. Crucial for understanding the transnational law-nature of global counterterrorism law is the peculiar relationship of this body of law to individuals. It is this relationship that ultimately distinguishes transnational law from (traditional) international law.22 It shall, therefore, be analyzed in detail here. How does transnational law on counter-terrorism affect individuals? What problems ensue when transnational law regulates the conduct of individuals? The following discussion shall be limited to law-making on the – what I want to call – ‘normative situation of non-state actors’, i.e. to shaping rights and obligations of non-state actors.23 First, the ‘regulatory nature’ of transnational counter-terrorism law shall be traced in a number of specific legal instruments (law-making treaties, law-making resolutions, and soft law instruments). Second, the question of the depth and the problem of direct effect of transnational regulatory norms will be analyzed. Third, the ensuing problem of – what shall be called here – ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ shall be discussed. The confines of space force me to limit the discussion to elements pertaining to the first part of the definition of ‘transnational law’, i.e. the relationship of transnational law to individuals. An analysis of the elements relating to the second part of the definition, i.e. the ‘cross border’-dimension of transnational law, must be left for later. 22 See, again, n 14. 23 For the purposes of this paper, a norm is considered to shape the normative situation of individuals if it is directed at permitting, proscribing or commanding human conduct. As stated in the Introduction, a socio-legal perspective on transnational law allows us to question misleading (doctrinal) dichotomies, such as, here, the dichotomy of ‘mediated’ and ‘unmediated’ law. While there is no world government creating or altering obligations with instant effect for all of us, global law-making on the normative situation of individuals is far more complex than what could be pressed into a simple model of ‘mediated-‘/’unmediated’-law. It is true that in an international society characterized by the predominance of state actors the realization of the aim of regulating the conduct of individuals will most often imply (at least) some concomitant act of law-making by states. This practice is, however, neither carved in stone nor does it prejudge its normative desirability. Furthermore, a socio-legal perspective on transnational law would favor – instead of employing a binary, ‘all-or-nothing’ solution – a continuum-explanation of the effect of cross-border law-making on the normative situation of individuals, on this see supra n 19. 21 7 I. Regulatory Law The concept of ‘transnational law’ captures one of the most significant recent developments in global law-making: the turn to the individual. In the context of counter-terrorism, this turn to the individual is of a different nature than, e.g., in international human rights law (which also is transnational). Whereas transnational law in the past has usually been of a rights-conferring nature, in the context of counter-terrorism (such as transnational organized crime), transnational law is about controlling the conduct of individuals. This move has been identified by Jacob Katz Cogan as the “regulatory turn” in international law.24 This means that the subjects of international have in recent times “at an unprecedented rate entered into agreements, passed resolutions, enacted laws, and created institutions and networks, formal and informal, that impose and enforce direct and indirect international duties upon individuals or that buttress a state’s authorities respecting those under and even beyond its territorial jurisdiction.”25 Since acts of terrorism are to a large part committed by non-state actors, law-making on counterterrorism law is a prime example for the “regulatory turn” in global law-making.26 Its ‘regulatory’ nature is a striking feature of transnational law-making on counter-terrorism. ‘Regulatory law’ shall be understood here as abstract-general norms (not necessarily made by a parliamentary body) creating obligations for non-state actors (private individuals and non-state entities).27 Subsequently, ‘transnational regulatory law’ refers to abstract-general norms with cross-border application or effect creating obligations for non-state actors. In principle, there are three instruments of transnational law-making used for shaping the normative situation of individuals by abstract-general norms: law-making treaties, (unilateral) law-making resolutions, and soft law instruments. See Jacob Katz Cogan, ‘The Regulatory Turn in International Law’ (2011) 52 Harv Int’l LJ 321, 346 (describing the historical impact of international criminal law and institutions in the early 1990s on the creation of direct obligations for individuals). 25 ibid 325. The “turn to the individual” is one important, though not the only defining feature of transnational law (the concept of transnational law is wider as it is not limited to international law but also encompasses domestic law with cross-border application or effect). On how to distinguish between ‘transnational’ and ‘international law’ see also n 14 (and accompanying text). 26 As Katz Cogan rightly stresses, the regulatory turn neither started with counter-terrorism law-making after the 9/11 attacks in the US nor is it, today, limited to it (given the international regulatory activity in fields such as ‘environmental law’, ‘organized crime’ and ‘violence against women’), see ibid 349–50. 27 cf ibid 324. Therefore, international human rights norms are not regulatory norms since they do not establish obligations but entitlements of individuals. 24 8 The bulk of transnational regulatory law in the field of counter-terrorism is contained in lawmaking treaties (transnational regulatory treaty-norms).28 There are currently 14 universal legal instruments and four amendments dealing with counter-terrorism.29 Some norms of these suppression conventions relate to the normative situation of individuals, i.e. they shape the obligations and, much less, rights of non-state actors. The ambition of designing the normative situation of individuals becomes clear from norms declaring that “[n]othing in this Convention shall affect other rights, obligations and responsibilities of ... individuals under international law ...”30 One way in which suppression conventions influence the normative situation of individuals is by requiring states to criminalize certain forms of individual conduct.31 Other transnational regulatory norms concern the introduction of particular professional duties (e.g., the duty to verify a customer32, the duty to keep records on transactions33). The normative situation of individuals is also shaped through law-making resolutions by the Security Council (transnational regulatory resolutions). The two (sole) examples of law-making resolutions so far, Security Council Resolutions 1373 (2001) and 1540 (2004), both ultimately target the normative situation of non-state actors in an abstract-general way. Even though both refer to “states” as formal addressees,34 their content regulates the conduct of non-state actors: For example, Security Council Resolution 1373 (2001) demands the criminalization of “the wilful provision or collection, by any means, directly or indirectly, of funds by their nationals or in their territories with the intention that the funds should be used, or in the knowledge that they are to be used, in order to carry out terrorist acts.”35 On the concept of a law-making treaty see Brunée (n 8), paras 4–6. See the list supra n 3. See <http://www.un.org/en/terrorism/instruments.shtml> accessed 13 May 2014. 30 For example, art 21 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism; art 4(1) of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism [emphasis mine]. 31 art 2(1) and (2) of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons, including Diplomatic Agents; art 1 and art 2 of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages; art 2 and art 4 of the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings; art 2 and art 4 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism; art 2 and art 5 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 32 art 18(1)(b) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 33 art 18(1)(b)(iv) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 34 Couched in the formula of “[d]ecides that all States shall”, see SC Res. 1373 (2001), paras 1 and 2; SC Res. 1540 (2004), para 2. 35 SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 1(b). Another example for transnational regulatory law is ibid, para 1(d) requiring States to “[p]rohibit their nationals or any persons and entities within their territories from making any funds, financial assets or economic resources or financial or other related services available, directly or indirectly, for the benefit of persons who commit or attempt to commit or facilitate or participate in the commission of terrorist acts, of entities 28 29 9 Similarly, Security Council Resolution 1540 (2004) mandates that states, “… shall adopt and enforce appropriate effective laws which prohibit any non-State actor to manufacture, acquire, possess, develop, transport, transfer or use nuclear, chemical or biological weapons and their means of delivery, in particular for terrorist purposes, as well as attempts to engage in any of the foregoing activities, participate in them as an accomplice, assist or finance them.”36 Apart from the two law-making resolutions, there are a few other examples of counter-terrorism resolutions where the Security Council (albeit in a more implicit and, above all, nonbinding way) undertook to shape the normative situation of individuals.37 Lastly, the normative situation of individuals is, albeit to a lesser extent, also shaped by soft law (transnational regulatory soft law provisions).38 The UN General Assembly has largely refrained from taking part in transnational regulatory activity. In other words, in its counter-terrorism resolutions, the General Assembly addresses the duties of states (often in a general way),39 reflects its own role as a coordinator and information provider,40 or as a initiator for further lawowned or controlled, directly or indirectly, by such persons and of persons and entities acting on behalf of or at the direction of such persons.” This was recently confirmed in SC Res. 2133 (2014), para 2. 36 SC Res. 1540 (2004), para 2. 37 Clearly, in SC Res. 1624 (2005), para 1: “Calls upon all States to adopt such measures as may be necessary and appropriate and in accordance with their obligations under international law to: (a) Prohibit by law incitement to commit a terrorist act or acts; (b) Prevent such conduct; (c) Deny safe haven to any persons with respect to whom there is credible and relevant information giving serious reasons for considering that they have been guilty of such conduct.” See also SC Res. 1455 (2003), para 5 (adopted under Ch VII of the UN Charter): “Calls upon all States to continue to take urgent steps to enforce and strengthen through legislative enactments or administrative measures, where appropriate, the measures imposed under domestic laws or regulations against their nationals and other individuals or entities operating in their territory, to prevent and punish violations of the measures referred to in paragraph 1 of this resolution [targeted sanctions against the Taliban and the Al-Qaida] …” [Emphasis omitted.] 38 On the idea of “international legislative soft law” see Andrew T. Guzman and Timothey L. Meyer, ‘Soft Law’ (University of Georgia School of Law Research Paper Series, Paper No 2014-17, May 2014) <http://ssrn.com/abstract=2437956> accessed 23 May 2014 (the idea of ‘international legislative soft law’ is “to send each other costly signals about how they [the states] interpret the content of binding legal obligations”, ibid 13; it pertains, however, to obligations of states, not of individuals). 39 For example, Measures to Eliminate International Terrorism, GA Res. 65/34, para 5: “Reiterates its call upon all States to adopt further measures in accordance with the Charter of the United Nations and the relevant provisions of international law, including international standards of human rights, to prevent terrorism and to strengthen international cooperation in combating terrorism and, to that end, to consider in particular the implementation of the measures set out in paragraphs 3 (a) to (f) of General Assembly resolution 51/210.” Ibid para 14: “Urges States to cooperate with the Secretary-General and with one another, as well as with interested intergovernmental organizations, with a view to ensuring, where appropriate within existing mandates, that technical and other expert advice is provided to those States requiring and requesting assistance in becoming parties to and implementing the conventions and protocols referred to in paragraph 13 above.” Ibid para 17: “Calls upon all States to cooperate to prevent and suppress terrorist acts.” [Emphasis omitted.] 40 GA Res. 65/34 para 3. 10 making,41 but it does not actively take part in regulatory transnational law-making.42 This may be a wise move, given that the General Assembly has – in the context of counter-terrorism – taken the role of a ‘constitutional gatekeeper’ as will be illustrated below.43 Indeed, it seems problematic for one institution to exercise both a regulatory function and a constitutional gatekeeping function. At the same time, new important actors that create transnational regulatory soft law provisions on counter-terrorism have entered the scene. An example is the Financial Action Task Force (FATF), an intergovernmental body established by the G-7 Summit Group in 1989.44 The FATF is an expert-driven transnational legislative network.45 The task of the FATF is “to set [soft law, T.A.] standards and promote effective implementation of legal, regulatory and operational measures for combating money laundering, terrorist financing and other related threats to the integrity of the international financial system.”46 A central soft law-instrument for counterterrorism financing is the FATF Special Recommendations on Terrorist Financing.47 Most of the nine recommendations are addressed to “states”, but some read clearly as transnational regulatory norms. Special Recommendation no. IV illustrates that: “If financial institutions, or other businesses or entities subject to anti-money laundering obligations, suspect or have reasonable grounds to suspect that funds are linked or related ibid para 8: “Expresses concern at the increase in incidents of kidnapping and hostage-taking with demands for ransom and/or political concessions by terrorist groups, and expresses the need to address this issue.” [Emphasis omitted.] 42 One exception is ibid para 9: “Urges States to ensure that their nationals or other persons and entities within their territory that wilfully provide or collect funds for the benefit of persons or entities who commit, or attempt to commit, facilitate or participate in the commission of terrorist acts are punished by penalties consistent with the grave nature of such acts.” 43 See Nigel White, ‘Terrorism, Security and International Law’ in Aidan Hehir, Natasha Kuhrt, Andrew Mumford (eds), International Law, Security and Ethics: Policy Challenges in the Post-9/11 World (Routledge 2011) 9, 22 (arguing that the General Assembly is “more concerned with a policy of trying to dissuade disaffected individuals from using terrorism by tackling the causes of terrorism”). 44 See <http://www.fatf-gafi.org/pages/aboutus/> accessed 19 May 2014. The FATF has – as of November 2013 – 36 members including two regional organizations. For an overview on FATF see Yee-Kuang Heng and Kenneth McDonagh, Risk, Global Governance and Security (Routledge 2009) 51–78. 45 See Dieter Kerwer and Rainer Hülsse, ‘How International Organizations Rule the World: The Case of the Financial Action Task Force on Money Laundering’ (2011) 2 Internat’l Org Stud 50, 55. 46 <http://www.fatf-gafi.org/pages/aboutus/> accessed 13 May 2014. On the FATF see Ilias Bantekas, ‘The International Law of Terrorist Financing’ (2003) 97 AJIL 315, 319 et passim. 47 FATF Special Recommendations on Terrorist Financing, October 2001 (rev. 2012) <http://www.fatfgafi.org/topics/fatfrecommendations/documents/ixspecialrecommendations.html> accessed 13 May 2014. 41 11 to, or are to be used for terrorism, terrorist acts or by terrorist organisations, they should be required to report promptly their suspicions to the competent authorities.”48 In sum, the regulatory nature of universal counter-terrorism law manifests itself in all three instruments of transnational law-making (transnational regulatory treaties, resolutions, and soft law) and must be considered a central feature to this body of law. II. Depth and Direct Effect In some areas of global counter-terrorism law we find particularly detailed norms setting out internationally preferred policy choices and instruments on the control of individual conduct.49 Suppression conventions do not only regulate individual conduct through criminalizationrequirements, but they also entail other elaborate state duties regarding the regulation of the conduct of individuals. For example, some conventions oblige states to introduce specific types of sanctions on individuals (such as freezing, forfeiture or seizure of funds)50, they require states to lay duties on private individuals and institutions and to give them an active role in the prevention of terrorism (such as the ‘know your customer’-strategy or reporting-obligations),51 or they require states to ensure the alleged offenders’ presence for the purpose of prosecution or extradition (in effect a duty to take the offender into custody).52 Some parts of transnational regulatory law seek to place particularly detailed duties on individuals. The 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism may serve as an example where it mandates states to require “financial institutions to maintain, for at least five years, all necessary records on transactions, both domestic or international.”53 The question of regulatory depth has important implications for human rights. In fact, human rights’ inspired reasoning should provide guidance on the question of what intensity or depth is required for transnational regulatory norms. The more transnational counter-terrorism law impacts important individual rights (such as the right to life and liberty), the more detailed its FATF Special Recommendations on Terrorist Financing, October 2001 (rev. 2012) <http://www.fatfgafi.org/topics/fatfrecommendations/documents/ixspecialrecommendations.html> accessed 13 May 2014, no. IV. See also ibid. no. VI, VII. 49 See Cogan (n 24) 338 note 74. 50 art 8(1) and art 8(2) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 51 art 18(1)(b) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 52 For example, art 10(2) of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 53 art 18(1)(b)(iv) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 48 12 norms should be in order to satisfy the principle of legality (in particular legal clarity).54 Transnational counter-terrorism law currently lives up to this demand only partially. For example, while some formulations used in suppression conventions regarding the elements of terrorist offenses (e.g. of possession of nuclear material, providing terrorist funding) are drafted with sufficiently high precision so as to fulfill the demands of legal clarity,55 other formulations are of a troubling vagueness (in particular provisions criminalizing membership in terrorist organizations).56 Another fundamentally important question is if transnational regulatory law can ever have – what some would call – ‘direct effect’ (or be ‘self-executing’, to use the U.S. terminology). This relates to the problem whether a norm containing international obligations may be enforced domestically (by the courts or the administration) without a preceding implementation act by the legislator.57 Generally speaking, the doctrine of direct effect (in most jurisdictions) requires that the international norm must be precise and unconditional, and that it is addressed to individuals (or other legal persons).58 There are two recent developments in the legal doctrine of On a transnational reading of the ‘principle of legality’ and its requirements see Anne Peters, Jenseits der Menschenrechte (Mohr Siebeck 2014) 70–81. The principle of legality and the requirement of precision of norms establishing criminal offenses is not derogable even in times of emergency, see Human Rights Committee, General Comment 29, States of Emergency (article 4), U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.11 (2001), para 7. 55 For example, art 2 (1)(b) of the International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism: “Any person commits an offence within the meaning of this Convention if that person by any means, directly or indirectly, unlawfully and willfully, provides or collects funds with the intention that they should be used or in the knowledge that they are to be used, in full or in part, in order to carry out: … Any other act intended to cause death or serious bodily injury to a civilian, or to any other person not taking an active part in the hostilities in a situation of armed conflict, when the purpose of such act, by its nature or context, is to intimidate a population, or to compel a government or an international organization to do or to abstain from doing any act.” 56 See Ben Saul, ‘Criminality and Terrorism’ in Ana María Salinas de Frías, Katja LH Samuel and Nigel D White (eds), Counter-Terrorism: International Law and Practice (OUP 2012) 133, 150-1. 57 See André Nollkaemper, National Courts and the International Rule of Law (OUP 2011) 118. For the doctrine of direct effect in the context of EU law see Joseph Weiler, ‘The Transformation of Europe’ (1991) 100 YLJ 2403, 2413–4. From a socio-legal perspective, the concept of direct effect is unsatisfactory for two reasons: First, it relies on the problematic dichotomy of an ‘inside-/outside’-law, consolidating an exceedingly artificial differentiation among legal sources. Here as in other cases, a socio-legal perspective on transnational law forces us to critique existing legal concepts. However, more often than not – on a doctrinal level – we will lack other more differentiated concepts (as, I think, in the case of direct effect). Secondly, the concept of direct effect pretends that there can be a clear-cut distinction to ‘indirect effect’ of legal norms. This position is, however, untenable, see supra n 84. 58 While these two conditions of direct effect are commonly required by domestic courts, there are differences to be noted (on the different criteria of direct effect see Karen Kaiser, ‘Treaties, Direct Applicability’ MEPIL (OUP 2013) <http://opil.ouplaw.com/home/epil> accessed 23 May 2014, para 6. Crucial for the purposes of this paper, there is no unity on the question whether the international norm must confer a right upon individuals in order to have direct effect (in favor of this position André Nollkaemper, ‘The Duality of Direct Effect of International Law’ (2014) 25 EJIL 105, 119). Contrary to that, I would argue that the conferral of rights to individuals by international norms is only a description of the situation in which direct effect is typically contemplated by domestic courts and administrations. Direct effect is, however, not conditioned upon the international norm conferring an individual right. It may well be that a (precise and unconditional) norm of international law addressed to individuals contains an obligation, and 54 13 direct effect that are relevant here: First, the doctrine of direct effect seems to be on the rise. It is true that the wide implications of direct effect as contemplated under EU law are still the exception and cannot be generalized for international law.59 Nevertheless, as André Nollkaemper has recently shown, the idea of direct effect (albeit in the limited context of rightsconferring international law, not regulatory law) is gaining ground internationally.60 Secondly, while traditional doctrine stressed the role of national law and institutions in the determination of direct effect, this too seems to change.61 As Anne Peters (among others) has argued, direct effect is also a matter for international law that can be decided upon by international courts and tribunals.62 Can transnational regulatory norms on counter-terrorism ever have direct effect? Regarding the first condition of direct effect, precision and unconditionality of the norms, some suppression conventions do contain regulatory provisions that seem clear enough so as to describe in sufficient detail the conduct required by individuals. As an example, one may refer to a provision contained in the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism which suggests to contracting parties to consider the adoption of the following measure: “Adopting regulations imposing on financial institutions the obligation to report promptly to the competent authorities all complex, unusual large transactions and unusual patterns of transactions, which have no apparent economic or obviously lawful should consequently be given direct effect in the domestic legal order. Examples for direct effect of (concreteindividual) obligations by international law can be found in the practice of international criminal courts. For example, the ICC-Statute provides for arrest warrants or summons with direct effect in the domestic legal systems, see art 58 ICC-Statute. See Shuichi Furuya, ‘Legal Effect of Rule of the International Criminal Tribunals and Court upon Individuals: Emerging International Law of Direct Effect’ (2000) 47 NILR 111. See, generally, Klabbers (n 121) 292 (“While different national traditions may reveal local differences, generally courts will look at whether the provision concerned seems directly to create rights or obligations for individuals …”) [my emphasis]. I am grateful to Anne Peters for a discussion of this point. 59 The doctrine of direct effect of EU law is famously connected with the Case C-26/62 Van Gend en Loos [1963] ECHR 1. See on this the articles published as part of ‘Revisiting Van Gend en Loos’ (Joint Symposium of the European Journal of International Law and International Journal of Constitutional Law) (2014) 25 EJIL (2014) 83–199 and (2014) 12 ICON 94– 213. 60 Nollkaemper (n 58) 107 (listing global jurisprudence relying on direct effect). 61 For the traditional view see Kaiser (n 58), para 6 (“The question whether a treaty is directly applicable is determined by domestic law and not by international law”), but see para 8 (“Although the question whether a treaty is directly applicable can thus ultimately only be answered by reference to domestic law, international law is not irrelevant. The domestic determination whether a treaty is directly applicable may depend upon the manner in which it has been interpreted on the international plane”). 62 Peters (n 54) 444 (with references to the literature). 14 purpose, without fear of assuming criminal or civil liability for breach of any restriction on disclosure of information if they report their suspicions in good faith.”63 While the content of this far-reaching regulation that contracting parties are required to adopt is prescribed in detail by the transnational norm (and is fleshed out in further detail by FATF-soft law), it clearly fails to meet the test of unconditionality. Already the wording shows that domestic implementation legislation is required. Additionally, take the provisions – central to all suppression conventions – on the criminalization of terrorist acts. Though these criminalizing norms set out the terrorist crimes in detail, they cannot be said to be unconditional so as to trigger direct effect: Direct effect of transnational norms criminalizing terrorism must fail as suppression conventions do not pronounce upon the precise legal consequences of the offenses. Consequently, all suppression conventions contain clauses on domestic (legislative) implementation of the criminalization provisions.64 Usually, direct effect will fail the second condition of direct effect, i.e. the condition that individuals must be the addressees of these norms. Indeed, international suppression conventions usually contain – what some would call – ‘mediated law’, i.e. law that has the state as addressee.65 The fact that, in practice, most transnational regulatory norms will not be directly effective does not mean, however, that direct effect of these norms must be ruled out on a principled account. Thus, should there be the enforcement of an international obligation of individuals without a preceding domestic implementation act? There are some good arguments against the doctrine of direct effect of transnational regulatory norms. Other than in the case of direct effect of individual rights, in the situation of transnational regulatory norms individual conduct is restricted or controlled by virtue of transnational law. Thus, the options for individual agency art 18(1)(b)(iii) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. For example: art 2 of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages (“Each State Party shall make the offences set forth in article 1 punishable by appropriate penalties which take into account the grave nature of those offences)”; art 4 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism (“Each State Party shall adopt such measures as may be necessary: (a) To establish as criminal offences under its domestic law the offences set forth in article 2; (b) To make those offences punishable by appropriate penalties which take into account the grave nature of the offences”). 65 cf Cogan (n 24) 328. I use the term ‘mediated law’ here because it reflects the legal situation of suppression conventions and for want of a more suitable description. However, from a socio-legal perspective on transnational law, the concept is inapt to capture the spectrum of impact of transnational law on the normative situation of individuals, see also my criticism supra n 23. 63 64 15 are reduced (and not increased as in transnational human rights law). If one does not want to argue on the basis of human rights-derived duties to protect other individuals (through the direct effect of transnational regulatory norms), a rights’ based argument for direct effect of regulatory norms is difficult to make. EU law supports this critical stance. Here, the problem of (‘compulsive’ or ‘reverse vertical’) direct effect has been discussed in the context of EU directives.66 In the case Kolpinghuis Nijmegen, the Court of Justice of the EU (CJEU; formerly European Court of Justice, ECJ) had to rule on the problem of ‘reverse vertical’ effect of an EU directive that had not been implemented in due time by the Netherlands.67 The case concerned the question whether the Netherlands could nevertheless rely in the domestic criminal proceedings on a provision of this directive against an individual. The CJEU declined that directives could create obligations for individuals (absent an implementing measure by the EU Member State).68 The arguments relied on the criminal law-context and dwelled on the principle of non-retroactivity of criminal norms and, more generally, the principle of legality.69 The Court also usually refers to the ‘nature’ of the law-making instrument stating that a “directive may not of itself impose obligations on an individual and … a provision of a directive may not be relied upon as such against a person before a national court.”70 There are, however, some more sympathetic voices on direct effect of transnational regulatory treaty norms. While it seems clear that direct effect of transnational regulatory norms must On the instrument of ‘directives’ in EU law see art 288 TFEU: “A directive shall be binding, as to the result to be achieved, upon each Member State to which it is addressed, but shall leave to the national authorities the choice of form and methods.” Directives are an “instrument of indirect resp. cooperative-/two-stage law-making”, see Matthias Ruffert, ‘Art. 288 AEUV’ in Gralf Calliess and id, EUV/AEUV (4ed Beck 2011) para 23. [my translation] 67 Case C-80/86 Kolpinghuis Nijmegen BV [1987] ECR 3969. The domestic criminal proceedings concerned a companyrun café that had sold as ‘mineral water’ a beverage consisting of tap-water and carbon dioxide. The directive provided that the EU Member States were to take steps to ensure that only water extracted from the ground of a Member State (and only that from officially authorized sources) could be sold as ‘mineral water’. The public prosecutor relied on this directive in criminal proceedings against the company despite the fact that the Netherlands had not yet implemented the directive. This situation of ‘reverse vertical effect’ of directives differs from the situation of ‘horizontal effect’ (or ‘third party effect’) of directives: The former plays out in the bilateral situation between the state and the individual (in criminal or administrative law proceedings), while the latter relates to a situation involving at least two private individuals. Just as in the case of ‘reverse vertical effect’ the CJEU has denied the ‘horizontal effect’ of directives for the reason that directives cannot, of themselves, establish duties for individuals, see Case C-152/84 Marshall v Southampton and South-West Hampshire Area Health Authority [1986] ECR 723. 68 Case C-80/86 Kolpinghuis Nijmegen BV [1987] ECR 3969, para 9. See also Joint Cases C-387/02, C-391/02 and C403/02 Silvio Berlusconi et al. [2005] ECR I-3624, paras 73–77. For a more permissive approach to ‘reverse vertical effect’ (outside the criminal law-context) see the Opinion of Advocate General Jacobs, Case C-456/98 Centrosteel Srl and Adipol GmbH [2000] I-6009, paras 34–5. 69 Opinion of Advocate General Kokott, Joint Cases C-387/02, C-391/02 and C-403/02 Silvio Berlusconi et al. [2005] ECR I-3568, paras 140–1. 70 Case C-80/86 Kolpinghuis Nijmegen BV [1987] ECR 3969, para 9. 66 16 remain the exception, it should not be discarded too early. In particular, direct effect of transnational regulatory norms seems less problematic outside the criminal law-context, when relating to other (civic) obligations of individuals.71 Anne Peters has convincingly argued that international treaties may only be interpreted as to confer obligations on individuals under the following restrictive conditions: First, the text must be clear on the question of conferring (precise and unconditional) obligations on individuals so as to satisfy the principle of legality, second, direct effect must serve the purpose of safeguarding important legal interests, and, third, there must be a heightened risk for a deficient implementation and enforcement in domestic law.72 In favor of direct effect of (sufficiently precise and unconditional) transnational regulatory norms one could argue along similar lines as for direct effect of rights-conferring transnational norms: First, direct effect of regulatory norms would both increase the effectiveness and the importance of transnational law.73 Domestic law enforcement agencies would be more actively drawn into the transnational legal process and the awareness for transnational public security law would be raised. Direct effect could contribute to enhance compliance with suppression conventions since more domestic actors would be directly involved in applying transnational norms (courts, administration). Secondly, in some cases direct effect may make resorting to the inherently problematic instrument of transnational regulatory resolutions (by the Security Council) unnecessary: If the international society could be sure that (some) transnational regulatory norms automatically become part of the ‘law of the land’, there would be less need for imposing these norms by the Security Council through lawmaking resolutions. Third, direct effect could lead to more consistency between transnational obligations and national law, “without their meaning being lost in translation.”74 What about direct effect of provisions in law-making resolutions by the Security Council? Can (or must) law-making resolutions by the Security Council be given direct domestic effect? Most resolutions by the Council – already by their wording – require the government to take additional steps of implementation.75 This problem is of practical relevance: If norms contained in law-making resolutions were directly applicable, they could act as a ‘legal basis’ for I am grateful to Anne Peters for referring me to this point. Peters (n 54) 79. 73 On the discussion of policy arguments for direct effect see John H. Jackson, ‘Status of Treaties in Domestic Legal Systems: A Policy Analysis’ (1992) 86 AJIL 310, 322 (who speaks of ‘direct applicability’). 74 For this argument concerning (ordinary) direct effect see Nollkaemper (n 58) 118. 75 Nico Krisch, ‘Art. 41’ in Bruno Simma/Daniel-Erasmus Khan/Georg Nolte/Andreas Paulus (eds), The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary on the UN Charter (OUP 2012) para 36. 71 72 17 restrictions of human rights.76 Some authors reject this: Nigel White has claimed that lawmaking resolutions are no “supranational legislation” with direct domestic effect.77 However, it is not clear why law-making resolutions could never be treated as having direct effect domestically.78 There seems to be no general or principle-based argument that would completely bar direct effect of transnational regulatory norms contained in Security Council resolutions. That direct effect of regulatory resolutions cannot be excluded does, however, not mean that there are reasons to embrace such an effect either. In my view, one focal point of discussion must be the quality of the norms (the other – the legitimacy of transnational regulatory resolutions – is addressed below). Though norms contained in law-making resolutions are not ‘treaty law’ in the strict sense of the term, they may be addressed as ‘secondary treaty norms’ and – with some modification – they should be subjected to similar criteria regarding direct effect.79 The decisive question is whether the regulatory norms contained in law-making resolutions are sufficiently precise and unconditional. The two existing law-making resolutions do not contain sufficiently precise and unconditional rules to be accorded direct effect. Also the wording of Resolutions 1373 (2001) and 1540 (2004) reflects the necessity for further implementation measures, e.g. when stating that laws should be adopted in accordance with the appropriate domestic procedures.80 Additionally, apart from the absence of a statement on the consequences of terrorist offences, the high level of precision required for a legal norm which could serve as a legal basis in criminal proceedings is clearly not met by any law-making resolution provision. Furthermore, the existence of special regimes monitoring the implementation of the law-making resolutions supports the finding that these resolutions are not designed to have direct effect domestically.81 In sum, while the possibility of direct effect of law-making resolutions by the Security Council should not be excluded in principle, in most See, e.g., art 8–11 ECHR which require that the interference be ‘prescribed by law.’ The question whether SC Res. 757 (1992) (and amending resolutions) against Serbia had direct effect and could be used as a legal basis in Irish law for restricting the right to freedom of possession (art 1 Prot 1 ECHR) was at issue in the Bosphorus case (ECtHR, 30 June 2005, no. 45036/98, para 145). On the problem of domestic implementation of a Security Council resolution and the correct identification of a ‘legal basis’ for interferences with Convention rights see also the Nada case (ECtHR, 12 September 2012, no 10593/08, para 173). 77 White (n 2) 72. 78 For a position favorable to the possibility of direct effect of Security Council resolutions see Peters (n 54) 452–3 (limiting the discussion to the situation of ‘targeted sanctions’). 79 Anne Peters, ‘Art. 25’ in Bruno Simma/Daniel-Erasmus Khan/Georg Nolte/Andreas Paulus (eds), The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary on the UN Charter (OUP 2012) para 47. 80 SC Res. 1540 (2004), para 2. 81 SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 6; SC Res. 1540 (2004), para 4. 76 18 cases even transnational regulatory resolutions will require the adoption of domestic legislation.82 Finally, the question arises whether there is anything similar to direct effect of transnational regulatory soft law. A legal concept that has ‘family resemblance’ with direct effect is that of ‘consistent interpretation’.83 In our context, this raises the question whether domestic courts and administrations may refer to transnational regulatory soft law when interpreting (domestic) obligations of non-state actors, in effect ‘harmonizing’ obligations contained in domestic law with transnational law.84 As transnational soft law instruments, like the FATF Special Recommendations, specify and in some ways complement both transnational regulatory treatynorms and transnational regulatory resolutions, it cannot be excluded that domestic courts and administrations may consult these for the purpose of facilitating consistent interpretation of domestic and transnational law.85 In sum, there are good arguments against direct effect of either treaty-based or law-making resolution-based transnational regulatory norms. This applies in the case of a criminal law context where the requirements of legal certainty and non-retroactivity are of great concern. In other fields of counter-terrorism, however, (e.g. controlling the conduct of financial institutions and other areas of prevention) a restrictive application of the doctrines of direct effect and, as a part of it, consistent interpretation may contribute to more efficient transnational law enforcement. For an in-depth analysis on the required implementation measures and potential problems see Bianchi (n 198) 892– 903 (relying on an analysis of country reports under Resolutions 1267 and 1373). 83 Some deny that ‘consistent interpretation’ can be consistently distinguished from direct effect, see Nollkaemper (n 58) 110. 84 In the EU law context, there is a ‘duty to consistent interpretation’ even with regard to EU soft law. See Case C322/88 Grimaldi [1989] ECR 4407, para 18: “The national courts are bound to take recommendations into consideration in order to decide disputes submitted to them, in particular where they cast light on the interpretation of national measures adopted to implement them or where they are designed to supplement binding Community provisions.” 85 This is the case e.g. in the Netherlands. See Joseph Fleuren, ‘The Application of Public International Law by Dutch Courts’ (2010) 57 Netherlands Int’l LR 245, 250 (with references to Dutch case law): “Although courts are not obliged to comply with them [rules of soft law], they frequently refer to those instruments when interpreting and applying binding rules of public international law.” 82 19 III. Constitutional Gatekeeping Finally, as transnational regulatory law increases, so does the need for what I call ‘constitutional gatekeeping’.86 ‘Constitutional gatekeeping’ is understood here as the function of monitoring ‘regulatory law’ on the basis of ‘constitutional principles’.87 This task becomes more complicated with transnational regulatory law where obligations of individuals (at least partially) originate in ‘foreign’ or ‘international’ law or – even more complicated – in (often non-transparent, exclusive) legislative networks. The problem of ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ raises some fundamental questions: What arguments can be made on a level of principle that ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ is necessary in the case of transnational regulatory norms? How do existing transnational regulatory norms relate to constitutional principles (such as human rights)? Which institution should exercise ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ on transnational regulatory norms?88 One objection that could be raised here is that ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ is unnecessary because transnational regulatory law is only ‘mediated law’ and that, therefore, individuals are not really directly affected by these norms. However, as transnational norms regulate the normative situation of individuals in ever more detail, the margin of implementation for states or regional organizations (such as the EU) diminishes. As an example, take again the provision in the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism that suggests to contracting parties to require “financial institutions to maintain, for at least five years, all necessary records on transactions.”89 Especially in cases where transnational regulatory norms seek to establish a common standard by setting minimum-level requirements the margin of legislative discretion in implementation decreases significantly. Jacob Katz Cogan argued that the gap between ‘mediated law’ and ‘unmediated law’ (i.e. directly effective law) Obviously, constitutional gatekeeping can take on many forms. The paradigm case of constitutional gatekeeping is judicial review, by having a court determine with final say what is in conformity with the Constitution and may properly be applied as ‘the law of the land’. However, judicial review is not suitable for all cases of transnational law. 87 By ‘constitutional principles’ I mean legal principles commonly established at the constitutional level or of a constitutional provenience, such as primarily human rights, principles of governance (rule of law, good governance norms) and principles on the political process (representation of interests and participation). As such, constitutional principles are “general and important norms whose main function is the attribution of the binary qualification of legal/illegal in light of overarching values”, von Bogdandy (n 7) 1912 (referring to Martti Koskenniemi). 88 My discussion leaves untouched the important question of what the source of these constitutional principles should be (domestic law or international law). 89 art 18(1)(b)(iv) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 86 20 continues to decrease.90 In sum, as mediated law can affect the normative position of non-state actors the problem of constitutional gatekeeping is triggered. Despite the necessity to infuse constitutional principles (in particular, human rights) into the process of creating transnational regulatory law, current practice does not look too bright. It can be noted, though, that suppression conventions today refer to human rights and “subjective international rights” (Anne Peters).91 Regarding transnational regulatory treaty-law, a few examples shall suffice. The early suppression conventions, such as the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons and the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages, contained “subjective international rights” for alleged offenders: For example, detained alleged offenders should be granted consular rights, such as “[t]o communicate without delay with the nearest appropriate representative of the State of which he is a national …”92 or the right to be visited by a state representative.93 Human rights protection in these early suppression conventions was addressed rather vaguely in general terms as a state duty to grant “fair treatment”.94 A step towards transnationalization was taken with the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings, requiring that “[a]ny person who is taken into custody or regarding whom any other measures are taken or proceedings are carried out pursuant to this Convention shall be guaranteed fair treatment, including enjoyment of all rights and guarantees in conformity with the law of the State in the territory of which that person is present and applicable provisions of international law, including international law of human rights.”95 Cogan (n 24) 349. See also my general remark supra n 23. On the conception of the “subjective international right” see Anne Peters, ‘Das subjective internationale Recht’ in Peter Häberle (ed), Jahrbuch des öffentlichen Rechts der Gegenwart 59 (2011) 411. 92 art 6(2)(a) of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons; art 6(3)(a) of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages. 93 art 6(2)(b) of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons; art 6(3)(b) of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages. 94 art 9 of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes against Internationally Protected Persons. Tellingly, the content of “fair treatment” is to be determined by domestic human rights, see art 8(2) of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages. 95 art 14 of the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings. For similar provisions see art 17 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism; art 12 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 90 91 21 It is clear, however, that these rights-related provisions target potential human rights’ violations on the implementation level, the level of transnational law-making itself is not covered. A cautious sign that all counter-terrorism efforts, be it on the national or the transnational level, must conform to international human rights is contained in the “Draft Comprehensive Convention against International Terrorism” (not in force), where the preamble in general terms recalls the “necessity of respecting human rights and international humanitarian law in the fight against terrorism.”96 If one accepts (which is far from settled) that there is a ‘normative hierarchy’ in international law,97 some provisions in recent suppression conventions may be interpreted as providing for the supremacy of constitutional principles over (regulatory) treaty law.98 This constitutionalist interpretation is, however, highly presumptive. The following can be gathered from this rather weak commitment to constitutional principles in the field of transnational regulatory treaty norms: If international law continues to embark on transnational regulatory law-making, the need for clear rules on normative hierarchy is reinforced.99 Similar considerations apply to law-making by the Security Council. It is known that transnational regulatory resolutions by the Security Council and constitutional principles cannot be squared easily. The initial law-making Resolution 1373 (2001) did not mention any duty to observe human rights (except in the very specific context of granting refugee status to asylumseekers).100 What is missing, therefore, in this resolution is the general pronouncement that domestic counter-terrorism measures must comply with international human rights’ standards. The false start induced some actors to regard human rights as a matter to be separated from global counter-terrorism. It is symptomatic that the Counter-Terrorism Committee (CTC), which is to monitor state-compliance with Resolution 1373 (2001), in the beginning viewed any human 96 Preamble of the Draft Comprehensive Convention against International Terrorism, UN Doc. A/59/894, Appendix II. On the problem of ‘normative hierarchy’ in international law see Martti Koskenniemi, ‘Hierarchy in International Law: A Sketch’ (1997) 8 EJIL 566; Dinah Shelton, ‘Normative Hierarchy in International Law’ (2006) 100 AJIL 291. 98 For example, art 21 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism: “Nothing in this Convention shall affect other rights, obligations and responsibilities of States and individuals under international law, in particular the purposes of the Charter of the United Nations, international humanitarian law and other relevant conventions.” 99 The introduction of a clear normative hierarchy is indeed demanded by – what I call – the ‘principle of integrity’ (the second structural principle of transnational law-making), see text accompanying n 222. 100 SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 3(f). 97 22 rights’ considerations to be outside the scope of its mandate.101 Once human rights were off the international agenda in the fight against terrorism, it proved difficult to introduce them. The Security Council reacted by adopting Resolution 1566 (2004) reminding states to ensure that “any measures taken to combat terrorism comply with all their obligations under international law, and [that the states] should adopt such measures in accordance with international law, in particular international human rights, refugee, and humanitarian law.”102 In law-making resolutions, reference to human rights has only been made in the Preamble, but not in operative paragraphs.103 As in the case of treaty-law, the problem remains of how to guarantee international human rights already at the level of transnational law-making. This touches upon the widely discussed problem (that is outside the scope of this paper) whether the Security Council is bound by international human rights.104 If one (as I do) accepts that the Security Council must obey international human rights, then the problem of ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ at the transnational level arises in full sway. If some form of transnational ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ is desirable or even necessary, who should perform it? A first actor that comes to mind is domestic courts. In the case of transnational regulatory treaty-norms, domestic courts are in the comfortable position to deny direct effect to norms they consider problematic on constitutional principle. In effect, domestic courts can use the concept of direct effect “as a shield” against treaty-norms to “protect domestic political organs and, more generally, domestic values” simply by rejecting one of the conditions of direct effect.105 However, it is questionable whether ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ at the domestic level is a feasible solution in practice. It cannot be ruled out that some states are ‘pressed’ to change their laws by powerful transnational actors (states or international organizations).106 For example, the U.S. imposes “special measures” on states that are unwilling See Kim Lane Scheppele, ‘Global security law and the challenge to constitutionalism after 9/11’ (2011) Public Law 353, 369 (quoting Sir Jeremy Greenstock, the first head of the Counter-Terrorism Committee); see also E.J. Flynn, ‘The Security Council’s Counter-Terrorism Committee and Human Rights’ (2007) 7 HRLR 371. 102 SC Res. 1566 (2004), Preamble. 103 But see SC Res. 1624 (2005), para 4 (this resolution was, however, not adopted under ch VII of the UN Charter). 104 For a thorough discussion see Peters (n 79). 105 Nollkaemper (n 58) 115–7, 121–4 (making clear that direct effect is not a “politics-free zone”). 106 Terence Halliday and Bruce Carruthers have described how international financial institutions pressed Indonesia to bring its bankruptcy law in conformity with international standards, see Terence C. Halliday and Bruce G. Carruthers, ‘The Recursivity of Law: Global Norm Making and National Law-making in the Globalization of 101 23 to participate in the global fight against counter-financing of terrorism.107 The threat of being cut off from access to the U.S. banking system has proven to be a powerful tool to ensure that states adopt transnational rules on counter-financing. In this situation it also seems unlikely that ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ by domestic courts would have enough ‘bite’. Similar problems arise in the case of Security Council law-making: In the absence of an example of a provision contained in a law-making resolution that has been given direct domestic effect it can only be speculated whether domestic courts would engage in prior constitutional review of transnational regulatory norms. Some domestic, regional and international courts have struggled to exercise ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ in relation to targeted sanctions by the Security Council.108 The task is not easier in relation to norms that enter the national sphere as rules originating in transnational regulatory resolutions. In all likelihood domestic courts will be deferential to transnational regulatory law by the Security Council. It suffices to say that, presently, it cannot be taken for granted that constitutional concerns about transnational regulatory norms will necessarily find a forum on the domestic level. It is important, therefore, that there exists some form of ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ already on the transnational level. Allen Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane have argued that global governance institutions such as the Security Council should – for legitimacy reasons – respect (at least, one would add) the “most widely recognized human rights.”109 However, as evidenced by the relatively late inclusion of human rights into law-making resolutions, the Security Council does not necessarily picture itself as a participant in a transnational legal discourse. This results from what Martti Koskenniemi has aptly characterized as “the absence of what might be called a legal culture” in the Security Council.110 A legal culture can be characterized as a “cultural form Corporate Insolvency Regimes’ (2007) 112 Am J of Sociology 1135, 1154–62. For the role of transnational standards in the reform of China’s law of criminal procedure see Sida Liu and Terence C. Halliday, ‘Recursivity in Legal Change: Lawyers and Reforms of China’s Criminal Procedure Law’ (2009) 34 Law & Social Inquiry 911. 107 Mariano-Florentino Cuéllar, ‘The Mismatch between State Power and State Capacity in Transnational Law Enforcement’ (2004) 22 Berkely J Int’l L 15, 38. 108 Some courts followed a deferential approach concerning ‘targeted sanctions’ by the Security Council, e.g. the Swiss Federal Court (Nada) and the General Court of the EU (Kadi). For an overview see Machiko Kanetake, ‘The Interfaces between the National and International Rule of Law: The Case of UN Targeted Sanctions’ (2012) 9 Int’l Org LR 267. 109 Allen Buchanan and Robert O. Keohane, ‘The Legitimacy of Global Governance Institutions’ (2006) 20 Ethics & Int’l Affairs 405, 419–435. 110 Martti Koskenniemi, ‘The Police in the Temple. Order, Justice and the UN: A Dialectical View’ (1995) 6 EJIL 325, 327. 24 that orders social relations and persons through particular legal values and practices.”111 If the Council continues to conform to a political mode of self-portrayal instead of a legal one there is no guarantee that even the “most widely recognized human rights” will guide and limit its lawmaking. The more detailed regulatory provisions of Security Council law-making are, the more urgent the respect for these rights becomes. A potential ‘constitutional gatekeeper’ is the UN General Assembly. The General Assembly acts as a ‘constitutional gatekeeper’ vis-à-vis the states. In this regard, the General Assembly regularly calls for the observance of “international human rights, refugee and humanitarian law” when implementing counter-terrorism measures in domestic law.112 The General Assembly also pointed to the “obligation of States … to respect certain rights as non-derogable in any circumstances”, making clear that counter-terrorism measures can never be treated as a human rights’-free zone.113 In particular, the General Assembly uses four means to carry out its ‘constitutional gatekeeping’-function: It points to absolute prohibitions (deriving from international human rights),114 it outlines state obligations flowing from international human rights in specific, recurrent counter-terrorism situations (e.g. deprivation of liberty, border control, extradition, profiling, interrogation)115 and it stresses the importance of particular international human rights in counter-terrorism (e.g. right to equality before the law, right to a fair trial, right to privacy, non-refoulement, right to an effective remedy and reparation, right to due process).116 Lastly, the General Assembly also stresses – in a truly transnational spirit – general conditions for domestic counter-terrorism legislation: It “urges States, while countering terrorism … [t]o ensure that their laws criminalizing acts of terrorism are accessible, formulated with precision, non-discriminatory, non-retroactive and in accordance with international law, including human rights law.”117 Kirsten Campbell, ‘The Making of Global Legal Culture and International Criminal Law’ (2013) 26 LJIL 155, 160 [emphasis in the original]. 112 See Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms while Countering Terrorism, GA Res. 65/221, 5 April 2011, para 4. 113 ibid, para 5. 114 ibid, para 6(a), (c), (d). 115 ibid, para 6(b), (h), (j), (k), (m), (n). 116 ibid, para 6(e), (f), (i), (o), (p). 117 ibid, para 6(l). See also ibid, para 6(q): “To shape and implement all counter-terrorism measures in accordance of gender equality and non-discrimination.” 111 25 The General Assembly potentially also acts as a ‘constitutional gatekeeper’ vis-à-vis the other UN organs, in particular the Security Council. In its resolution on the “Protection on Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms while Countering Terrorism”, the General Assembly stated “the need to continue ensuring that fair and clear procedures under the United Nations terrorism-related sanctions regime are strengthened in order to enhance their efficiency and transparency, and welcomes and encourages the ongoing efforts of the Security Council in support of these objectives, including by establishing an office of the ombudsperson and continuing to review all the names of individuals and entities in the regime, while emphasizing the importance of these sanctions in countering terrorism.”118 However, all of these statements are rather weak and are far from any real monitoring of transnational regulatory law. It seems that the UN General Assembly has not exploited its full potential as a meaningful ‘constitutional gatekeeper’ yet.119 Other potent ‘constitutional gatekeepers’ (such as a world court) are not in sight.120 In sum, ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ at the transnational level – while ever more important with the increase of transnational regulatory instruments – is largely absent. B. Reasons for Transnational Cooperation on Counter-Terrorism Why do we have something like transnational counter-terrorism law? This question cannot be answered by doctrinal analysis in a satisfactory way. Instead, socio-legal analysis provides a rewarding perspective. Drawing, as I indicated in the introduction, on Joel Trachtman’s approach the initial question can be reformulated as follows: Why do states cooperate on matters of transnational terrorism? Surely, the reasons for international cooperation are a traditional ‘battle ground’ of the sociology of international law.121 Trachtman’s cooperationparadigm and method provides helpful guidance on this. Trachtman approaches international cooperation from a public welfarist angle, claiming that the subjects of the international society ibid, para 9. For criticism of the role of UN General Assembly in counter-terrorism see White (n 2) 62. 120 One may contemplate an emerging transnational public or transnational civil society (e.g. in the form of NGOs, internet fora, international newspapers) exercising (additional) ‘constitutional gatekeeping’-functions. It is one benefit of transnational law to allow for the inclusion private actors both in the law-making as well as, arguably, in the monitoring process. 121 For a useful introduction and overview on the theories of international cooperation see Jan Klabbers, An Introduction to International Institutional Law (2nd ed. CUP 2009) 25–31. 118 119 26 (states, in his case) use international law “to better their lot.”122 Thus, according to Trachtman, international cooperation takes place when it increases public welfare gains for the participating members of the international society.123 Applying Trachtman to the problem at hand, what are the welfare gains expected from cooperation on global terrorism? I. Efficiency Gains A first straightforward reason why there is international cooperation on counter-terrorism is (expected) efficiency gains. Transnational terrorism, by definition, crosses borders, as it targets victims of foreign states, and often affects interests of more than one state. Efficiency gains through international cooperation are relatively easily made: For example, by sharing information on transnational terrorists, costly (and sometimes even impossible) intelligence collection of each state on its own can be avoided.124 Furthermore, international cooperation allows for joint counter-terrorism investigation and actions: Surveillance missions on the High Seas where joint counter-terrorism action may reduce the costs of each participating state while at the same time ensuring the global movement of people and goods are a suitable example.125 Furthermore, some have argued that cooperation tends to increase the ambitions of participants, i.e. joint efforts would lead to an increased efficiency in the performance of a task.126 In sum, international cooperation allows us to expect the generation of better results in the prevention (and prosecution) of terrorist crimes. Of course, not all members of the international society (states, for that matter) are affected by transnational terrorism to the same degree. Those states more affected by transnational terrorism are likely to anticipate more efficiency gains from increased international cooperation Trachtman (n 10) 22–3. According to Trachtman, the content of public welfare is determined by domestic procedures (in democratic states through voting and elections), see ibid 23. The liberal assumption that participants want to increase their (absolute) welfare gains is, however, open to criticism, see Joseph M. Grieco, ‘Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation’ (1988) 42 International Organization 485, 487 (defending the realist position that states are “positional”, not “atomistic”; instead, there are two “major barriers to international cooperation: state concerns about cheating and state concerns about relative achievement of gains.”) 123 See Trachtman (n 10) 23. 124 For transatlantic intelligence information sharing between the U.S. and the EU see Christian Kaunert, ‘The External Dimension of EU Counter-Terrorism Relations: Competences, Interests, and Institutions’ (2010) 22 Terrorism and Political Violence 41, 55. In many cases, foreign intelligence services will lack even the capabilities to collect information on transnational terrorism on their own and therefore instead rely on international intelligence networks. See Jennifer E. Sims, ‘Foreign Intelligence Liaison: Devils, Deals, and Details’ (2006) 19 Int’l J of Intelligence and CounterIntelligence 195. 125 See on this Yonah Alexander and Tyler B. Richardson, Terror on the High Seas: From Piracy to Strategic Challenge (ABC-Clio 2009). 126 Wynn Rees, Transatlantic Counter-Terrorism Cooperation: The New Imperative (Routledge 2006) 30. 122 27 than less affected states. Furthermore, asymmetries in size or power of the actors (i.e. the capability to counter threats of transnational terrorism) are likely to affect each state’s willingness to cooperate.127 For example, while Switzerland has good reasons to consider itself a safe place as regards transnational terrorism, participation in European and international security networks, e.g. Schengen, has always been a political priority.128 A central reason is the limited capacity of Switzerland to independently ensure its own security.129 II. External Effects Efficiency gains are not the only reason why states cooperate on matters of counter-terrorism. The way states deal with problems of global terrorism is likely to produce (negative) external effects, i.e. adverse effects caused by one state affect another state.130 In the context of counterterrorism, some speak of “security externalities”.131 The following hypothetical may serve as an example: State A has a common border with state B. Due to a lack in professionalism and capacity, state B does not provide for effective transport security and border control which causes increased spending in state A in order to prevent terrorists from infiltrating the country from across the border.132 The inaction (or incapacity) of state B, thus, has external effects in state A. In times of global interdependence the potential impact of negative externalities is ever more powerful and widespread.133 Cooperation is a way to address or “internalize” some negative externalities. To get back to the example of states A and B: State A would enter into bilateral cooperation with state B or seek assistance from other states or the international society.134 127 On this point see generally Daniel W. Drezner, ‘Globalization and Policy Convergence’ (2001) 3 Int’l Studies R 53, 60. On the terrorism-situation in Switzerland see the 2013 Situation Report of the Federal Intelligence Service (FIS) <http://www.vbs.admin.ch/internet/vbs/en/home/documentation/publication/snd_publ.html> accessed 19 May 2014. 129 This is especially true regarding the protection of Switzerland’s airspace which currently partly relies on foreign contributions, e.g. by France and Italy. 130 On external effects and international law see Jeffrey L. Dunoff and Joel P. Trachtman, ‘Economic Analysis of International Law’ (1999) 24 Yale J Int’l L 1, 14–6. 131 Howard C. Kunreuther and Erwann O. Michel-Kerjan, ‘The Economics of Security Externalities: Assessing, Managing and Benefiting from Global Interdependent Risks’ (2007) <http://www.opim.wharton.upenn.edu/risk/papers/> accessed 19 May 2014. 132 This is the case, e.g., with the Tajik-Afghan border. See the 2012 Country Reports on Terrorism (United States Department of State Publication, Bureau of Counterterrorism, May 2013) <http://www.state.gov/j/ct/rls/crt/2012/index.htm> accessed 19 May 2014. 133 As Howard C. Kunreuther and Erwann O. Michel-Kerjan write, “[p]eople, organizations and/or governments may not realize how their failure to operate can affect a large number of agents, often rippling far beyond their direct influence” (n 131) 3. 134 The latter happened in the case of Tajikistan: “Tajikistan has made progress in improving border security with bilateral and multilateral assistance, though effectively policing the Tajik/Afghan border is a monumental task 128 28 In the situation of external effects, collective action problems arise, such as deterrence races between states (by overspending of each state on counter-terrorism and thus deflecting terrorist attacks to third countries) and free-riding problems (where one state anticipates another state to act that is either more powerful or more likely to be affected by an otherwise shared terrorist threat).135 Cooperation in the form of international law is an attempt to address these collective action problems. Rules on jurisdiction that are contained in all international counter-terrorism conventions are a good example: By allocating jurisdiction, these international rules “establish congruence between decision-making authority and the effects of the exercise of authority.”136 Requiring contracting states to establish jurisdiction over certain terrorist offences (as suppression conventions do), thus, eliminates a free-riding problem: Contracting states are required to act upon allegations of terrorist offenses regardless of whether they anticipate another state to act as well. III. Weakest Link Public Good In international legal literature, the global public goods-taxonomy has recently gained some currency.137 It can be useful for understanding global law-making efforts on counter-terrorism as well. The production of global public goods (and the problems surrounding that) is another reason why actors engage in international cooperation. ‘Public goods’ are defined by two characteristics: non-rivalry (i.e. the good may be consumed by one actor without diminishing its availability to others) and non-excludability (i.e. no actor may be excluded from consumption regardless whether she contributed to its production or not).138 The following goods are, among others, discussed under the heading of ‘global public goods’: environment, health, cultural heritage, knowledge and information, peace and security.139 requiring more resources and capabilities than the Tajik government has. The International Organization on Migration and the OSCE worked to improve travel document security. The OSCE has funding to link Tajikistan’s existing passport data scanners at airports and land ports of entry to the Interpol database”, 2012 Country Reports on Terrorism (n 132) 171–2. 135 Todd Sandler, ‘Collective Action and Transnational Terrorism’ (2003) 26 World Economy 779, 781. 136 Trachtman (n 10) 26. 137 See Inge Kaul, ‘Global Public Goods: Explaining their Underprovision’ (2012) 15 J of Int’l Econ L 729; Daniel Bodansky, ‘What’s in a concept? Global Public Goods, International Law, and Legitimacy’ (2012) 23 EJIL 651; Gregory C. Shaffer, ‘International Law and Global Public Goods in a Legal Pluralist World’ (2012) 23 EJIL 669. 138 Bodansky (n 137) 652. 139 This list is based on the case studies in Inge Kaul, Isabelle Grunberg and Marc A. Stern (eds), Global Public Goods: International Cooperation in the 21st Century (OUP 1999). 29 Public goods are usually distinguished on the basis of differences in their provision: aggregate effort public goods, single best effort public goods, and weakest link public goods.140 Aggregate effort public goods are those that can only be produced together (by all states). Daniel Bodansky gives the example of climate change mitigation. Climate change mitigation is “a function of the total level of greenhouse gas emissions reductions achieved by all of the countries in the world.”141 Single best effort public goods are unrelated to cooperative efforts, but instead “depend on the single best effort of an individual actor or small group of actors”, such as scientific discoveries.142 Most relevant in the context of counter-terrorism is the third category of weakest link public goods. The provision of such goods does not depend on aggregate effort, but on the performance of the “weakest” member of a community.143 An example is the prevention of global pandemics: The success of the eradication of smallpox could be “undone by a single actor that fails to do its part.”144 Some efforts by states in the global fight against terrorism can be considered a weakest link global public good. For example, Nico Krisch has recently discussed countering terrorist financing as a weakest link good.145 Efforts by individual states to curb terrorist financing are seriously hampered (if not oftentimes futile) as soon as only a few states do not comply with the global rules.146 The same is true for nuclear terrorism.147 All attempts by the international society to prevent nuclear terrorism are in vain if only one state defects. C. Techniques of Transnational Law-Making on Counter-Terrorism How is transnational counter-terrorism law created? It is not an institutional analysis on actors and procedures that shall be undertaken here. Instead, the last part of this paper deals with the creation of transnational counter-terrorism law from a socio-legal perspective. What are the techniques of cooperation (using law-making) in the field of global counter-terrorism? See on this Bodansky (n 137), 658–65. ibid 658–9. 142 ibid 663. 143 ibid 660. 144 ibid 661. 145 Nico Krisch, ‘The Decay of Consent: International Law in an Age of Global Public Goods’ (2014) 108 AJIL 1, 20–5. 146 This is a reason why the international society seeks to eliminate ‘safe havens’ for terrorists, see SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 2(c) (“Decides also that all States shall ... [d]eny safe haven to those who finance, plan, support, or commit terrorist acts, or provide safe havens”) [emphasis omitted]. 147 For an economics approach to nuclear terrorism as a weakest link-problem see Stefano Barbieri and David A. Malueg, ‘Securing Security when Terrorists Attack the 'Weakest Link'’ (November 26, 2013) <http://ssrn.com/abstract=1981319> accessed 19 May 2014. 140 141 30 I. Harmonization One technique of transnational law-making is ‘harmonization’. By ‘harmonization’ I mean the reduction of differences between legal norms of different (national) origin through a binding legal act with cross-border application. The typical instrument for harmonization of domestic and international norms is an international treaty. The level of harmonization envisaged by the international legal norm may vary ranging from ‘minimum harmonization’ to ‘full harmonization’ or ‘unification’.148 Outside special regimes (like the EU) international lawmaking by harmonization is a consensual, non-hierarchical type of cooperation.149 Legal harmonization on the international plane is historically associated with private law. Already in the late 19th century, scholars advocated cross-border harmonization or unification of private laws.150 The rationale behind private law harmonization is an expected reduction of transaction costs, i.e. the cost of participating in the market.151 Despite of evident differences to private law harmonization, I nevertheless believe that the project of harmonization of other fields (such as public and criminal law) can benefit from the experiences made with private law harmonization. From the 20th century onwards, the idea of harmonization is not limited to private law any longer, but relates to all sorts of legal fields, such as labor law (especially work health and safety laws),152 environmental law,153 health law154 etc. Harmonization of criminal law has become an issue as well.155 In particular, harmonization of counter-terrorism law has resulted in significant See Martin Gebauer, ‘Unification and Harmonization of Laws’ MEPIL (OUP 2009) <http://opil.ouplaw.com/home/epil> accessed 23 May 2014, para 24. 149 See Katharina Holzinger and Christoph Knill, ‘Causes and Conditions of Cross-National Policy Convergence’ (2005) 12 J of Eur Pub Pol’y 775, 782. 150 See Gebauer (n 148), para 2. 151 Katharina Pistor, ‘The Standardization of Law and Its Effect on Developing Economies’ (2002) 50 Am J of Comp L 97. 152 Junji Nakagawa, International Harmonization of Economic Regulation (OUP 2011) ch 6. 153 Katharina Holzinger, Christoph Knill and Thomas Sommerer, ‘Environmental Policy Convergence: The Impact of International Harmonization, Transnational Communication, and Regulatory Competition’ (2008) 62 Int’l Org 553 (finding empirically an “impressive degree of environmental policy convergence” between 24 industrialized countries between 1970 and 2000, mainly caused by international harmonization). 154 On the need to internationally harmonize public health standards see David P. Fiedler, ‘A Globalized Theory of Public Health Law’ (2002) 30 J of Law, Medicine & Ethics 150, 153. Similarly, Lawrence O. Gostin and Allyn L. Taylor, ‘Global Health Law: A Definition and Grand Challenges’ (2008) 1 Public Health Ethics 53, 61 (pointing out that in global health law it is not so much international standard-setting that is problematic but implementation and coordination). 155 See Neil Boister, ‘Transnational Criminal Law?’ (2003) 14 EJIL 953. For the special context of harmonization of criminal law the EU see Valsamis Mitsilegas, EU Criminal Law (Hart 2009) 59–114. 148 31 efforts by states in the past decade.156 In the EU, this objective has found its clearest expression in the ‘Framework Decision on Counter-Terrorism’ of 2002 the purpose of which is to introduce minimum rules concerning terrorist offences in the EU Member States.157 Some European institutions continue to pressure for more harmonization of domestic counter-terrorism law.158 On the international level, the harmonization of counter-terrorism law is less openly framed as an objective of international law-making. Nevertheless, harmonization is at least partially the result of transnational law-making processes. The tendency of harmonization can be noted when consulting the US Country Reports on Terrorism.159 To make harmonization processes more efficient, there are numerous examples of best practices guides on how to transpose UN counterterrorism law into domestic law.160 On a bilateral level, there are currently ongoing negotiations between the EU and the US on harmonizing existing counter-terrorism laws.161 Why does it make sense – under the cooperation-paradigm – to harmonize counter-terrorism laws? First, Peter Andreas and Ethan Nadelmann expressed the underlying rationale of harmonization as follows: “The capacity of a state to suppress transnational criminality depends greatly on the extent to which its criminal law norms conform with or vary from those of Kimmo Nuotio, ‘Terrorism as a Catalyst for the Emergence, Harmonization and Reform of Criminal Law’ (2006) 4 J of Int’l Crim Justice 998, 1012 (discussing counter-terrorism efforts by the UN, EU and the Council of Europe and concluding that “the goal of harmonizing national laws is difficult to reach”). 157 Council Framework Decision on Combating Terrorism [2002] OJ L 164/3. 158 For example, Eurojust, see Michèle Coinsx, ‘Strengthening Interstate Cooperation: The Eurojust Experience’ in Ana María Salinas de Frías, Katja Samuel, Nigel D White (eds), Counter-Terrorism: International Law and Practice (OUP 2012) 965, 989. The task of Eurojust is, according to art 85 TFEU, “to support and strengthen coordination and cooperation between national investigating and prosecuting authorities in relation to serious crime affecting two or more Member States.” 159 For example, a U.S. Country Report states that Bosnia and Hercegovina harmonized its criminal code with the EU and UN legal framework on counter-terrorism, 2012 Country Reports on Terrorism (n 132) 63. Similarly, for Montenegro see the 2008 Country Reports on Terrorism (United States Department of State Publication, Bureau of Counterterrorism, April 2009) < http://www.state.gov/j/ct/rls/crt/2008/index.htm> accessed 19 May 2014, 85. 160 Domestic implementation of suppression conventions and law-making resolutions by the Security Council is often aided by ‘model laws’. In the field of counter-terrorism, the UN Counter Terrorism Committee (CTC) has the mandate to prepare model laws for the areas covered in Resolution 1373 (2001), SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 6; SC Res. 1377 (2001) (inviting the CTC to explore the “promotion of best-practice in the areas covered by resolution 1373 (2001), including the preparation of model laws as appropriate”). UNODC has prepared a comprehensive manual intended as model for domestic counter-terrorism legislation <https://www.unodc.org/tldb/en/model_laws_treaties.html> accessed 19 May 2014. Model laws encompass suggestions for norms on terrorism in general but also relate to specific issues, such as the financing of terrorism. These model laws have proved to be a valuable tool for developing domestic counter-terrorism capacities, see C.A. Ward, ‘Building Capacity to Combat International Terrorism: The Role of the United Nations Security Council’ (2003) 8 J of Conflict & Security L 289, 303. 161 See Kristin Archick, ‘U.S.-EU Cooperation Against Terrorism’ (2013) <https://www.fas.org/sgp/crs/row/RS22030.pdf> accessed 19 May 2014. 156 32 others.”162 Harmonization of counter-terrorism law is, in other words, a way to decrease information deficits about foreign law and to create opportunities and obligations for future cooperation and for further approximation of policies. Therefore, international counter-terrorism conventions contain several clauses dealing with cooperation obligations or opportunities. Take, e.g., the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages stipulating in Art. 4 (b) that “States Parties shall co-operate in the prevention of the offences set forth in article 1, particularly by … [e]xchanging information and co-ordinating the taking of administrative and other measures as appropriate to prevent the commission of those offences.”163 Second, another objective of harmonization is improving the law. Harmonization is about substituting domestic norms with “better” transnational norms.164 For example, counterterrorism norms usually seek to enhance the security-capacities of states facing transnational terrorism threats. Examples are the duty to establish jurisdiction (over certain terrorist crimes),165 the duty to criminalize particular terrorist crimes,166 or the duty to establish the liability of legal persons.167 In all of these cases, international law-making serves to strengthen domestic counterterrorism capacities. Third, harmonization of counter-terrorism laws is a way to internalize “security externalities” since collective action problems may be better addressed by cooperative rulemaking than by individual solutions.168 In the situation of a shared threat, i.e. transnational terrorism, harmonization of counter-terrorism law is a way to manage legal risks and thus ensuring more Peter Andreas and Ethan Nadelmann, Policing the Globe: Criminalization and Crime Control in International Relations (OUP 2006) 227. 163 art 4(b) of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages. 164 For this argument in a commercial law context see Paul B. Stephan, ‘The Futility of Unification and Harmonization in International Commercial Law’ (1999) 39 Va J Int’ L 743, 748. According to Trachtman’s welfarist approach followed here, “better” rules are those that increase the (domestically determined) public welfare, see text accompanying n 122. 165 For example, art 3 of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes Against Internationally Protected Persons; art 5 of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages; art 6 of the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings; art 7 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism; art 9 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 166 Examples: art 2(2) of the 1973 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of Crimes Against Internationally Protected Persons; art 2 of the 1979 International Convention against the Taking of Hostages; art 4 of the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings; art 4 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism; art 5 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 167 Example: art 5 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 168 On this argument in a commercial law context see Stephan (n 164) 749. On “security externalities” see above Part B.II. 162 33 stability in an important field of public policy.169 For example, transnational counter-terrorism instruments usually require all contracting states to adopt laws criminalizing specific acts of terrorism, e.g. the acquisition of nuclear material by private persons.170 Here, transnational law sets a narrow margin for differences in domestic law-making in order to minimize potential negative external effects. To take another example, the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism requires that contracting states adopt the “necessary measures to enable a legal entity located in its territory or organized under its laws to be held liable when a person responsible for the management or control of that legal entity has, in that capacity, committed an offence set forth in article 2.”171 This norm entails harmonization in relation to the goal that is to be achieved, namely, that legal persons may be held liable for violations of legal norms on counter-financing of terrorism (it is, however, flexible as to the means how to achieve that goal).172 In that way, the potential for adverse external effects caused by differences in domestic legal systems regarding the sanctioning of legal persons are reduced, though full harmonization is avoided. In practice, transnational harmonization of counter-terrorism norms is a complex, often impossible task. As the U.S. Counter-Terrorism Reports show, there are great differences among the states regarding compliance with transnational norms on counter-terrorism.173 What are the problems of harmonizing counter-terrorism law? A first obstacle to harmonization is the lack of a shared understanding of the phenomenon to be regulated. For example, states will only be willing to share information or to offer assistance when they can be sure that the act in question is in fact to be considered as an act of terrorism. However, it is well-known that terrorism is Adapting an argument by Stephan (n 164) 746. art 5 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 171 art 5(1) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 172 According to art 5(3) of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism liability may be operationalized through criminal, civil or administrative sanctions. 173 For example, the 2012 U.S. Country Report on Terrorism criticized Turkey for its “continued lack of progress in adequately criminalizing terrorist financing and establishing a legal framework to freeze terrorist assets” (n 132) 100, Kuwait and Yemen for lacking a legal framework for prosecuting terrorism-related crimes altogether (n 132) 126 resp 150. See Katja Samuel, ‘The Rule of Law Framework and its Lacunae: Normative, Interpretative, and/or Policy Created?’ in Ana María Salinas de Frías, Katja Samuel, Nigel D White (eds), Counter-Terrorism: International Law and Practice (OUP 2012) 14, 18 (noting the “poor harmonization of national, regional, and international anti-terrorism lawmaking and instruments”). 169 170 34 notoriously difficult to define174 and, in fact, the international society has not agreed upon a universal definition of it.175 A second problem is the diversity of criminal law systems and criminal law cultures. For example, even if a universal definition of transnational terrorism existed, it would still be doubtful whether liberal democracies would share information gained in counter-terrorism operations with non-liberal states.176 Even within the EU, the diversity of criminal law systems is a severe obstacle to harmonization. The EU Member States have been reluctant to include counter-terrorism among the truly supranational issues (i.e. opening up counter-terrorism for EU harmonization).177 Instead, the method used is ‘mutual recognition’, i.e. the recognition and enforcement of foreign criminal law, as second-best alternative to harmonization of counterterrorism laws.178 A third problem with harmonization of counter-terrorism law in its practical application is that it is non-holistic, i.e. it focuses on individual norms rather than employing a systemic approach: Harmonization affects some norms directly, but leaves other domestic norms that are only indirectly implicated untouched. This may lead to unwanted systemic imbalances. The introduction of the corporate liability norm mentioned above by the 1999 Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism is an example.179 Implanting such a norm into a legal system may require changes in the law of criminal procedure and, at least as importantly, It has been pointed out that the difficulty of definition is due to the fact that “various institutions compete for the most appropriate approach”, Mathieu Deflem, ‘Terrorism’ in J. Mitchell Miller (ed), 21st Century Criminology: A Reference Handbook (Sage 2009) 533. On the definition of terrorism followed in this paper see n 1. 175 As a (second-best) way out, international law-making relies on sectoral, context-specific definitions of terrorism, e.g. acts of financing of terrorism or acts of nuclear terrorism, see art 2 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism and art 2 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. Due to the freedom-fighter problem it has been deemed necessary to include provisions in international conventions that further delineate the concept, e.g. clauses stating that terrorist acts “are under no circumstances justifiable by considerations of a political, philosophical, ideological, racial, ethnic, religious or other similar nature”, see, e.g., art 5 of the 1997 International Convention for the Suppression of Terrorist Bombings and art 6 of the 2005 International Convention for the Suppression of Acts of Nuclear Terrorism. 176 The reverse situation is also problematic: should courts in liberal states accept evidence allegedly gained from torture in non-liberal states? For a recent case on the problem see Othman (Abu Qatada) v UK App no 8139/09 (ECHR, 17 January 2012). See generally Tobias Thienel, ‘The Admissibility of Evidence Obtained by Torture Under International Law’ (2006) 17 EJIL 349. 177 Javier Argomaniz, ‘Post-9/11 Institutionalisation of European Union Counterterrorism: Emergence, Acceleration and Inertia’ (2009) 18 Eur Security 151. 178 Oldrich Bures, EU Counterterrorism Policy: A Paper Tiger? (Ashgate 2011) 168. On transnational mutual recognition in general see Kalypso Nicolaidis and Gregory Shaffer, ‘Transnational Mutual Recognition Regimes: Governance Without Global Government’ (2005) 68 L and Contemp Prob 263. 179 art 5 of the 1999 International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism. 174 35 should be counter-balanced by domestic human rights (e.g. the extension of some procedural human rights to legal persons). Transnational harmonization efforts do not sufficiently pay tribute to these (indirect) consequences. II. Imposition A second technique of transnational law-making is the ‘imposition’ of legal norms. By imposition I mean the unilateral transfer of a norm through a legally binding act with crossborder application. An instrument for the imposition of transnational norms is a resolution (by an organ of an international organization, paradigmatically the UN Security Council). ‘Imposition’ presupposes a hierarchical relationship, built on an asymmetrical distribution of power.180 Due to its coercive nature, imposition as a technique of transnational law-making is inherently problematic. Law-making through imposition is still a great exception given that the international legal order is based on the equality of states.181 Nevertheless, the Security Council has – with its counterterrorism agenda – entered into a “legislative phase” and, in particular, Resolutions 1373 (2001) and 1540 (2004) are of a legislative character since they were unilaterally imposed through a binding decision of the Security Council.182 This classification depends on how ‘law-making’ in the context of the UN is understood. One has a fairly clear image of what law-making means in the domestic context, usually involving an elected or at least democratically accountable body which promulgates binding rules satisfying certain rule of law-criteria.183 There are obvious differences to domestic law-making: Security Council law-making resolutions are addressed to states only, not – as the case with domestic law-making – to individuals.184 Furthermore, the procedure of adoption is much less formal than that of domestic laws which often require multiple hearings.185 There is no such thing as an accepted ‘theory’ of law-making with regard to Holzinger/Knill (n 149) 781. art 2(1) UN-Charter. 182 Jose E Alvarez, ‘Hegemonic International Law Revisited’ (2003) 97 AJIL 873, 874. Examples from the vivid discussion in the literature on Security Council law-making include: Paul C Szasz, ‘The Security Council Starts Legislating’ (2002) 96 AJIL 901; Eric Rosand, ‘The Security Council as “Global Legislator”: Ultra Vires or Ultra Innovative?’ (2005) 28 Fordham Int’l LJ 542; Stefan Talmon, ‘The Security Council as World Legislature’ (2005) 99 AJIL 175. 183 Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law (Yale University Press 1964) 46. 184 Roberto Lavalle, ‘A Novel, if Akward, Exercise in International Law-Making: Security Council Resolution 1540 (2004)’ (2004) 51 Netherlands Int’l LR 411, 415. 185 Talmon (n 182) 186–188 (stating that resolutions are usually prepared in the course of informal consultations of the members and often adopted without a debate). 180 181 36 the UN.186 The simple reason is that until now such a theory was dispensable since law-making was not conceived of as a possible competence of a UN organ. Note, however, that the Council has never used the label of law-making for any of its acts. Instead of formally distinguishing these acts the Council has cast them in the familiar style of decision-making in the form of “resolutions”.187 In general, legislating is not something that international organizations regularly do.188 The term ‘law-making’ should, therefore, be used with caution in the context of the Security Council action. Although a rare phenomenon in practice, Eric Rosand has claimed that there is a “widely accepted definition of law-making” with regard to the UN.189 According to this definition, the act must be unilateral, create or modify a legal norm of a general nature, and be directed to an indeterminate group of addresses while capable of repeated application over time.190 In short, the formal imposition of norms relates to the unilateral transfer of abstract-general norms of a binding character.191 The element of ‘generality’ refers to the addressees: As the Colombian delegate to the Security Council, Maggie Farley, stated, a legislative resolution “does not name a single country, society or group of people.”192 Rather, it targets all states. ‘Abstractness’ relates to the subject-matter of legislative resolutions: They are not concerned with a specific situation or individualized conduct, but rather with a certain type of agency (e.g., financing of terrorism).193 Resolutions 1373 (2001) and 1540 (2004) meet these criteria. They are ‘general’ in the sense of obligating ‘all states’.194 Furthermore, they are ‘abstract’ in the sense that they do not target a The absence of meaningful ‘theories of law-making’ on the domestic level has often been noted: Jeremy Waldron, The Dignity of Law-making (Cambridge University Press 1999) 1 (“There is nothing about legislatures or law-making in modern philosophical jurisprudence remotely comparable to the discussion of judicial decision-making. No one seems to have seen the need for a theory or ideal-type that would do for law-making what Ronald Dworkin’s model judge, “Hercules,” purports to do for adjudicative reasoning”). 187 Some have held that the Security Council was unaware of the novelty of its action when adopting SC Res. 1373 (2001), see Szasz (n 182) 905. 188 Klabbers (n 121) 187 (pointing, i.a., to art 12 of the Chicago Convention which entrusts the International Civil Aviation Authority with the power to establish rules regulating aircraft flying over the High Seas). 189 Rosand (n 182) 545 note 11. 190 ibid (referring, i.a., on the classic treatment in E Yemin, Legislative Powers in the United Nations and its Specialized Agencies). See also Brunée (n 8) paras 48–51 (normative act promulgated unilaterally by an authorized organ and containing general, abstract and directly binding legal norms). 191 See, e.g., Talmon (n 182) 176; Anne Peters, ‘Art. 24’ in Bruno Simma/Daniel-Erasmus Khan/Georg Nolte/Andreas Paulus (eds), The Charter of the United Nations: A Commentary on the UN Charter (OUP 2012) para 67. 192 Maggie Farley, ‘U.N. Measure Requires Every Nation to Take Steps Against Terrorism’ (L.A. Times, 28 September, 2001), at A6, quoted by Talmon (n 182) 177 note 20. 193 See Matthew Happold, ‘Security Council Resolution 1373 and the Constitution of the United Nations’ (2003) 16 LJIL 593, 598. 194 SC Res. 1373 (2001), paras 1–6; SC Res. 1540 (2004), paras 1–5; 8‒10. Interestingly, contrary to the paragraphs just mentioned, para 6 of the latter resolution only refers to “Member States”. 186 37 specific situation, but aspects of terrorism as a particularly harmful form of human agency. In this regard, Resolution 1373 (2001) concerns the financing of terrorism, while Resolution 1540 (2004) seeks to prevent nuclear, chemical or biological weapons falling into illicit hands, especially that of terrorists. In line with their abstract-general nature, these resolutions do not provide for a time-limit of application.195 They remain in force until repealed by the Security Council and apply to an indefinite number of cases. In the cooperation-paradigm used here, when does imposition of counter-terrorism law make sense, and why? A pure efficiency-focus is too short-sighted in this case. While it may be more efficient to rely on the ‘fast track’-procedure of Security Council norm-imposition, there are serious concerns from a legitimacy-perspective: It seems to be clear that norm-imposition by the Security Council, in the absence of a UN Charter amendment, may not replace the existing procedures of international law-making, i.e. treaty law or customary international law.196 The imposition of norms by the Security Council must, in other words, remain of a subsidiary character only. This is sometimes addressed as ‘urgency-requirement’197 or as the existence of a ‘need for general law’.198 The urgency-requirement is met, in exceptional circumstances only, if the ordinary procedure – despite the existence of an actual ‘threat to the peace’ – has either failed (e.g., because a minority of states withholds their consent preventing an international solution) or is unlikely to produce an efficient result (e.g. unspecific norms).199 Apart from this pragmatic reason, imposition can be an effective way to handle weakest linksituations: If the success of a counter-terrorism measure depends on the performance of the weakest link, the rest of the international society has a particularly strong reason to force that state to adopt the necessary rules. Talmon (n 182) 176. To install law-making by resolutions on equal footing with the other two law-making procedures – treaty-law and customary law – would in my view require a formal amendment of the UN Charter (and other treaties). One reason is that the legal architecture of the UN Charter contemplates ch VII-law as ‘crisis law’ (in particular, by virtue of art 39 of the UN Charter). Security Council law-making without a ‘crisis’ of sorts is illegitimate. But, of course, one can argue that severe cooperation deficiencies among states on a vital global public good constitute a ‘crisis’. 197 See Rosand (n 182) 579‒80 (“new and urgent threat not addressed by existing treaty regimes”). 198 See Andrea Bianchi, ‘Assessing the Effectiveness of the UN Security Council’s Anti-terrorism Measures: The Quest for Legitimacy and Cohesion’ (2006) 17 EJIL 881, 888. 199 See ibid (stating that customary law-making would – in the case of terrorism – not have produced sufficiently precise norms, requiring, e.g., asset freezing or the criminalization of certain acts). 195 196 38 III. Diffusion Diffusion of law refers to consensual, non-binding law-making (or, rather, norm dispersion) with transnational effect through transnational legislative networks.200 Transnational lawmaking by diffusion differs from harmonization in that the creation of conformity with transnational legal norms does not follow from a legally binding formal act but from informal interaction. Diffusion is also to be distinguished from imposition in that there is no hierarchical relationship between the ‘law-creator’ and the ‘law-recipient’. Transnational networks engaged in the diffusion of norms are, in principle, conceivable for any of the three branches of government: there may be legislative, administrative, and judicial networks.201 In most areas, administrations and the judiciary seem to be more successful in establishing transnational networks (e.g. on human rights, on environmental issues). However, in the field of counter-terrorism, legislative networks have become crucial platforms for the dispersion of transnational norms.202 At UN level e.g., the Counter Terrorism Committee (CTC) provides legislative assistance to domestic law-making bodies.203 Another transnational legislative network of increasing importance is the Organization for Security and Co-Operation in Europe (OSCE).204 Various sub-units of the OSCE offer assistance to national legislators in drafting legislation to criminalize terrorist offenses and to ensure its conformity with human rights.205 Another network that has become active in the field of counter-terrorism is NATO (North On ‘diffusion of law’ see Richard M. Buxbaum, ‘Law, Diffusion of’ in Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes (eds), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences (Elsevier 2004) 1. 201 See Martin S. Flaherty, ‘Judicial Foreign Relations Authority After 9/11’ (2011/12) 56 New York Law School LR 119, 140–144 (distinguishing between “executive”, “legislative”, and “judicial globalization”). 202 Flaherty (n 201) 142. 203 <http://www.un.org/en/sc/ctc/> accessed 19 May 2014. 204 On the OSCE as a transnational legislative network see Anne-Marie Slaugther, A New World Order (Princeton University Press 2004) 128. The OSCE is a regional arrangement under ch VIII of the UN Charter, comprising 57 state parties <http://www.osce.org/who> accessed 19 May 2014. 205 Ministerial Statement on Supporting the United Nations Global Counter-Terrorism Strategy (MC.DOC/3/07), para 22: “The Office for Democratic Institutions and Human Rights will continue to assist participating States, at their request, in ensuring that their counter-terrorism initiatives are human rights compliant, pursuant to their OSCE commitments. The ODIHR will continue to offer technical assistance and advice on the human rights aspects of the drafting and implementation of national law-making aimed at countering the threats posed by terrorism, violent extremism and radicalization that lead to terrorism, and will continue to facilitate dialogue between State and nongovernmental actors with a view to exploring areas of co-operation and mutual assistance (…).” See also the Ministerial Council Ministerial Statement on Supporting and Promoting the International Legal Framework against Terrorism (MC.DOC/5/06): “We will continue exchanging information, including through the Permanent Council and the Forum for Security Co-operation, on progress achieved in becoming party to international, regional and bilateral legal instruments against terrorism and on legal co-operation in criminal matters, as well as on developments in the national law-making related to terrorism.” 200 39 Atlantic Treaty Organization) which established a network of civil experts on terrorism.206 Additionally, there are other regional organizations that form transnational legislative networks on counter-terrorism, e.g., the Intergovernmental Authority on Development in Eastern Africa (IGAD)207 or the Inter-American Committee on Terrorism (CICTE).208 Besides international and regional organizations, there are individual states, such as the U.S. that became engaged in transnational norm diffusion through governmental aid programs.209 What are the reasons for law-making by diffusion under the cooperation-paradigm? In a rather broad sketch one may distinguish between the following rationales for diffusion of norms through transnational legislative networks: transnational learning and (a flexible, informal type of) transnational problem-solving.210 First, where global or regional norms do not command the adoption of a specific solution or regulatory design (as is often the case), transnational lawmaking by diffusion allows learning from the experience of others. The rationale of transnational learning assumes that governments pose themselves the question: “Under what circumstances and to what extend would a programme now in effect elsewhere also work here?”211 Take the example of material support to terrorism. International law requires the criminalization of material support to terrorism, but leaves open which conception of material support states adopt.212 Consequently, there are very broad approaches to material support, like On NATO’s counter-terrorism activities see <http://www.nato.int/cps/en/natolive/topics_77646.htm?> accessed 19 May 2014. However, NATO’s activity is primarily on an operative, non-legislative level, e.g. conducting a number of counter-terrorism activities, such Operation Active Endeavour (OAE, a maritime surveillance operation in the Mediterranean). 207 IGAD has, in 2006, launched the “Capacity Building Programme against Terrorism” (ICPAT), see <http://www.icpat.org/> accessed 19 May 2014. Enhancing counter-terrorism law-making in the region is one of the core activities pursued by ICPAT, ‘Enhancing Judicial Measures’ <http://www.icpat.org/index.php/areas-ofactivity-mainmenu-106> accessed 19 May 2014. See also Rodrigo Tavares, Regional Security: The Capacity of International Organizations (Routledge 2010) 52. 208 On the role of CICTE in providing legal assistance on counter-terrorism see José Raul Perales, ‘Crime, Violence, and Security in the Caribbean’ (Woodrow Wilson Center Update on the Americas, June 2008, No. 29) <http://theislamistsarecoming.wilsoncenter.org/sites/default/files/lap.cc.29.pdf> accessed 19 May 2014, 4. 209 See Leslie E. King and Judson M. Ray, ‘Developing Transnational Law Enforcement Cooperation: The FBI Training Initiative’ (2000) 16 J of Contemp Crim Justice 386. 210 This is an adaptation to the legal context of the reasons given by Holzinger/Knill (n 149) 782–6. 211 Holzinger/Knill (n 149) 783 (quoting R. Rose). 212 See GA Res. 60/288, II § 2: “We resolve to undertake the following measures to prevent and combat terrorism, in particular by denying terrorists access to the means to carry out their attacks, to their targets and to the desired impact of their attacks: To cooperate fully in the fight against terrorism, in accordance with our obligations under international law, in order to find, deny safe haven and bring to justice, on the basis of the principle of extradite or prosecute, any person who supports, facilitates, participates or attempts to participate in the financing, planning, preparation or perpetration of terrorist acts or provides safe havens.” SC Res. 1373 (2001), para 2: “Decides also that all States shall: (c) Deny safe haven to those who finance, plan, support, or commit terrorist acts, or provide safe havens; (e) Ensure that any person who participates in the financing, planning, preparation or perpetration of terrorist 206 40 in the U.S., where even peaceful aid (such as provision of training on how to use international law for resolving disputes peacefully) may be criminalized.213 On the other side of the spectrum, there are narrower approaches to material support, for example in the case of Canada. Canadian law requires that the contribution must be “made for the purpose of enhancing the ability of any terrorist group to facilitate or carry out a terrorist activity.”214 The Canadian approach to material support is more appropriate, if the social goal of a society is to cut off terrorist organizations from the means to carry out their attacks while at the same time allowing for “socially acceptable” forms of interaction with, say, charity organizations. On the other hand, the U.S. approach is more appropriate, if any contribution to a terrorist organization is considered of potential ‘dual use’ (i.e. furthering both legitimate and criminal aims). Second, transnational legislative networks allow for flexible and informal transnational problem-solving. According to Holzinger and Knill transnational problem-solving is “driven by the joint development of common problem perceptions and solutions to similar domestic problems and their subsequent adoption at the domestic level. Transnational problem-solving typically occurs within transnational élite networks or epistemic communities, defined as networks of policy experts who share common principled beliefs over ends, causal beliefs over means and common standards of accruing and testing new knowledge.”215 What are the problems with norm diffusion through transnational legislative networks? Transnational learning assumes that governments act rationally, i.e. that they are willing to change existing policies for ‘superior’ ones.216 Given that diffusion is an informal way of transnational law-making, its success largely depends on the political will of the relevant actors of the international society. The ability to engage in transnational learning furthermore presupposes the existence of a certain level of existing homogeneity between the legal systems acts or in supporting terrorist acts is brought to justice and ensure that, in addition to any other measures against them, such terrorist acts are established as serious criminal offences in domestic laws and regulations and that the punishment duly reflects the seriousness of such terrorist acts; (f) Afford one another the greatest measure of assistance in connection with criminal investigations or criminal proceedings relating to the financing or support of terrorist acts, including assistance in obtaining evidence in their possession necessary for the proceedings.” 213 Holder v. Humanitarian Law Project, 561 U.S. 1 (2010). 214 s 83.18(1) of the Canadian Criminal Code. 215 Holzinger/Knill (n 149) 783 (referring to P.M. Haas). 216 ibid. 41 of the law-creator and the law-recipient.217 Finally, transnational learning is only possible if governments are actually able to collect all the necessary information on foreign regulatory designs.218 Not all of these conditions are likely to be fulfilled in every case. Subsequently, counting on transnational learning may be a rather optimistic rationale. Transnational problem-solving as the other rationale underlying diffusion of norms through transnational legislative networks has its drawbacks, too. As Louis de Koker writes in a critique on the FATF (that could be generalized for the situation of other transnational legislative networks), “[t]he FATF remains an exclusive club representing a number of influential nations. Its decision-taking processes are largely non-transparent, even to the participants and citizens of its member nations. It acts as an expert group but its expertise is generally not backed by verifiable data and its experts are generally anonymous.”219 In other words, while the problem with transnational learning is its unreliability, the problem of transnational problem-solving is the lack of formalized law-making processes and the exclusivity of membership in transnational networks. Conclusion: Two Principles of Transnational Counter-Terrorism Law-Making A principled approach on global counter-terrorism law-making tries to find regularities in the creation of a set of legal materials that has evolved over the last 50 years. Only in the recent decade, however, has universal counter-terrorism law-making emerged as a truly experimental field of international law-making. In this situation, structural principles help to explain the manifestations of a legal practice.220 On the basis of the present analysis, two main structural principles of global counter-terrorism law-making stand out. The first principle of transnational counter-terrorism law-making is the ‘principle of integration’. Given the (particular) nature of the reasons for cooperation in this field (in particular, anticipated disastrous external effects of deficient domestic law-making on terrorism as well as See ibid 791. See ibid 783. 219 Louis de Koker, ‘Applying Anti-Money Laundering Laws to Fight Corruption’ in Adam Graycar and Russell G. Smith (eds), Handbook of Global Research and Practice in Corruption (Edward Elgar Publishing 2011) 340, 356. 220 On the concept and use of structural principles see again supra n 7. 217 218 42 weakest link-problems), international law-making had to get closer to the normative situation of individuals ‘on the ground’. The principle of integration contends that the gap between ‘the international’ and ‘the domestic’ in counter-terrorism is increasingly bridged through an innovative body of law. This principle has a procedural as well as material dimension. Procedurally, the principle of integration manifests itself in efforts to make cooperation among the actors of the international society more efficient, entailing unorthodox unilateral corrections of cooperation deficiencies (in the form of transnational regulatory resolutions). The principle of integration helps to understand the phenomenon of imposition of transnational norms as well as the flourishing of transnational legal networks that assist in shaping and disseminating these norms. Finally, the principle of integration has the potential to inform the management of direct effect of transnational regulatory norms, and further account for the tendency to enhance the link between the domestic legal order and transnational law in counter-terrorism. Materially, the principle of integration captures the tendency to make international law look more like ordinary (domestic) statute-law.221 The principle of integration, here, helps to appreciate the depth of the transnational norms we face in global counter-terrorism law. Integration reflects the ambition of global law-making to set out ‘model laws’ that can be transposed without great effort into domestic legal orders. Much in this context has been left untouched by the present analysis. A point for further research would be to look at the principle of integration in more detail: What examples can be found for successful ‘integrative’ law-making, when did it fail and why? How does the principle of integration manage the problem of the diversity of different legal orders? Are there examples for integration on counter-terrorism at the domestic level? The second principle is that of integrity.222 It has been argued here that transnational lawmaking triggers the need to safeguard the ‘integrity’ of law-making already at the transnational level of norm-creation, not just at the level of domestic implementation. The ‘principle of integrity’ requires global counter-terrorism law-making to be informed and constrained by See Cogan (n 24) 351 (observing that some suppression conventions “read like domestic statutes”). My use of the ‘principle of integrity’ differs from that of Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin’s principle of integrity (as applied to the lawmaker) establishes the requirement to make the “total set of laws morally coherent”, id, Law’s Empire (Belknap Press 1986) 176. This theory-specific use is not what is meant here. Rather, the principle of integrity refers to the practice of establishing as well as the need for conformity of transnational law-making with higher (normative) standards. 221 222 43 concerns of transnational constitutionalism.223 The actors involved in transnational law-making are only starting to recognize what the principle of integrity entails in practical terms. Some developments can be explained by the principle of integrity of law-making, e.g. the reference to human rights and other standards in suppression conventions and recent law-making resolutions by the Security Council. However, it cannot be sufficiently stressed that the consequences of the principle of integrity in transnational law-making are just beginning to be drawn. This seems to be the field that should attract most attention of scholars: How – on a level of principle – can it be argued that transnational law-making must be accompanied (guided and limited) by a conception of ‘transnational constitutionalism’? What are the sources of transnational constitutionalism? What is required by the notion of transnational constitutionalism? Are there signs of transnational constitutionalism in the practice of domestic or international regulatory law-making? How effective is ‘constitutional gatekeeping’ by actors of an emerging transnational civil society? Transnational law-making on counter-terrorism is a challenge to international law as we know it, both in practice as well as on a level of principle. As much as it gives rise to a renewed belief in the importance of international law, it also radically exposes its imperfections. For conceptions of transnational constitutionalism see Wen-Chen Chang and Jiunn-rong Yeh, ‘The Emergence of Transnational Constitutionalism: Its Features, Challenges and Solutions’ (2008) 27 Penn State Int’l LR 89; Nicolas Tsagourias (ed), Transnational Constitutionalism: International and European Perspectives (CUP 2010). 223 44
© Copyright 2024