1 Yousuf Hasan Writing Sample PhD Application Jan. 2014 The Newman Problem: Why Carnap’s Ramsey-Approach to Scientific Theories Requires a Reconceptualization Abstract The Newman objection seems to render any form of pure epistemic structuralism nearly trivial or incoherent. I will show that Carnap’s reinvention of the Ramsey-sentence approach to scientific theories commits him to a form of structuralism that is subject to Newman’s pessimistic result. Because the Ramsey device used by Carnap seems to provide an elegant and promising way to explain away the problem of “surplus meaning” and make sense of ‘analyticity’ in the theoretical language of science, I propose that we conceptually reengineer Carnap’s Ramsey-approach in a way that the Newman objection is no longer a problem. 1. Introduction In this paper, I will argue that Carnap’s Ramsey-approach to scientific theories requires a reconstruction in order to sidestep the Newman problem. Carnap proposes a rational reconstruction of a scientific theory as a conjunction of a Ramsey-sentence and a Carnapsentence. The Ramsey-sentence is intended to express the factual content of the theory; while, the Carnap-sentence is proposed as an analytic-postulate. The union of these two sentences logically imply the entire theory without naming any theoretical entities. However, Newman’s theorem in effect shows that any form of pure epistemic structuralism is either almost trivial or incoherent. If the Ramsey-sentence of a theory is empirically adequate, then it is trivially true so long as only a cardinality constraint is satisfied. Given that synthetic knowledge about the 2 world is not supposed to be trivial (or knowable a priori), the Ramsey-sentence is an unfaithful representation of the synthetic content of a theory. A conceptual reengineering of the Ramseysentence approach is needed in order to remedy the problem. I have divided this paper into two parts. Each part is further divided into two sections. In part one, I will setup Carnap’s Ramsey reconstruction of theories. First, I will explain the philosophical motivations for Carnap’s Ramsey-sentence approach. Later, I elaborate why, for Carnap, the Ramsey-language is a useful proposal for a rational reconstruction of our scientific language. In the second part of the paper, I will argue that a reformulation of the Ramseylanguage is needed to circumvent the Newman problem. I begin by explaining why Carnap’s use of Ramsey’s device is subject to Newman’s structural pessimism. Afterwards, I show that Newman’s objection is a serious problem for Carnap’s Ramsification of theories. I conclude that an adequate expression for the synthetic content of a theory must result in a conceptual modification of the Ramsey-sentence approach to scientific theories. 2. Philosophical Motivation For The Ramsey Approach Carnap of the Aufbau (1928) is traditionally interpreted as carrying out a reductive empiricists’ project.1 According to this interpretation, Carnap’s Aufbau system is principally motivated by the semantic reduction of t-terms and t-predicates to o-terms and o-predicates. A complete translation of theoretical discourse to the observational language through the use of explicit definitions would preserve the meaningfulness of the theoretical language by being reduced to the confirmable language of observation. Moreover, there would be no need to 1 Quine, W. V. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” (1951); revised edition (1961), pp. 13 3 inflate ontology beyond o-entities and logico-mathematical entities. T-discourse would simply be a short-hand way of speaking about o-entities. The newer interpretations, however, by Friedman2 and others suggest that Carnap of the Aufbau is primarily concerned by the reduction of theoretical discourse to the pure structure of the world. Carnap, they say, interpreted the world as a mathematical entity constituted of quadruples of real numbers.3 All physical magnitudes such as electromagnetic fields or even space-time points are conceived as n-tuples of reals for Carnap. However, they insist, this does not imply that Carnap was an antirealistic with respect to t-entities. He never denies the existence of t-entities. Instead, by not naming t-entities, Carnap is in effect proposing a rational reconstruction of the world that is purported to be metaphysically neutral. Friedman’s structuralist interpretation of Carnap is not only consistent with the Carnap of Testability and Meaning (1936)4, but it especially accounts for the later works of Carnap—the Carnap of ESO (1956) and Beobactungssprache und Theoretische Sprache (1958)5 in particular— where eventually Carnap reinvents the Ramsey-sentence approach to scientific theories. While Friedman’s interpretation of Carnap’s motivation behind his Aufbau is more nuanced, there is, however, prima facie evidence for a reductive empiricist construal of Carnap. As it has been emphasized by Quine and Goodman,6 Carnap of the Aufbau attempted to use explicit reduction 2 Friedman, M. “Reconsidering Aufbau.” Reconsidering Logical Positivism (1999). Pincock, C. “Carnap, Russell, and the External World.” The Cambridge Companion to Carnap (2007), pp. 118. 4 Carnap, Rudolf. “Introduction.” Testability and Meaning (1936), pp. 423. Carnap considered the old verification as an explication of a theory of meaning. Even the replacement of the verification theory by confirmation (1936) was “far from being an entirely satisfactory solution” (Carnap 423). 5 Carnap, Rudolf. “Beobactungssprache und Theoretische Sprache.” reprinted with an introduction by Ed. Stathis Psillos. “Rudolf Carnap’s ‘Theoretical Concepts in Science’.” (2000), pp. 162. 6 Leitgeb, Hannes. “New Life for Carnap’s Aufbau.” (2011), pp. 2. 3 4 sentences to connect the theoretical discourse to the observational language in a way that made t-discourse completely connected to experience. But notice that Carnap’s emphasis is on “experience” instead of “the given”. This suggests that a straight-forward phenomenalistic reading of Carnap may be overly simplistic. For Carnap did not give special status to “the given”. It is better to interpret Carnap as a conventionalist who was open to the adoption of both a phenomenalistic language and a physicalistic (or thing) language for the conceptualization of the world. There is no reliance on “the given” as a basis for scientific objectivity. As Leigeb elaborates, “[e]xperiences may be the contents of particular mental states or they may be particular mental states themselves” (Leigeb 269). The autopsychological was never given the epistemic privilege of being considered more secure than the knowledge of physical things. Nowhere in the Aufbau did “Carnap [employ] the traditional vocabulary of ‘certainty’, ‘justification’, ‘doubt’, and so on” (Friedman 119). For these reasons, the motivation behind Carnap’s Aufbau system is better understood as a structuralist explication for a metaphysically neutral construction of the world. In the explicative project of reducing t-discourse to the observational language (1928), Carnap realized that as a matter of empirical fact the nature of reductive sentences could not be analytic.7 As a result, t-discourse could not be defined in terms of o-vocabulary in the explicit sense. This lead Carnap in the mid-thirties to adopt a more workable proposal for the purposes of connecting t-discourse to the more familiar (and less problematic) o-discourse. Strict verification was replaced by confirmation (1936). Under Quine’s phenomenalistic reading of 7 For a survey of problems that lead to Carnap’s realization, Cf. Psillos, Stathis. “Carnap’s Neutralism.” Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (1999), pp. 39-46. 5 Carnap, this meant a complete failure of the Aufbau project and any reasonable hopes for a reductive empiricist project. While it is true that no amount of reductive sentences would suffice for explicitly defining t-discourse in virtue of the o-language, the resulting “surplus meaning” problem disappears with Carnap’s Ramsey-approach to scientific theories (1958). By constructing a Ramsey-sentence in the Ramsey-language extension of the ordinary language, it is possible to express a scientific theory (with all of its observable consequences) without having to require any t-vocabulary. There is no “surplus meaning” problem since there are no theoretical terms to speak of that are not fully interpreted (since a complete translation is untenable). The reinvention of the Ramsey-sentence by Carnap makes good sense under Friedman’s structuralist motivations for Carnap’s Aufbau system. The Ramsey-approach is a result of Carnap’s explicationary approach to scientific theories. 3. The Ramsey-Language Proposal The Carnap of 19588 and 19649 proposed and elaborated an extension of the ordinary observation language LO to the Ramsey-language LR. Unlike LO, LR is sufficiently powerful to express what has come to be known as the Ramsey-sentence of a theory. Not only does LR entails VO (o-terms and o-predicates) and elementary logic/mathematics, it contains essentially “the whole of mathematics” (Carnap 253), including very complicated logic. Being an extension 8 Carnap, Rudolf. “Beobactungssprache und Theoretische Sprache.” Dialectica, (1958); reprinted with introduction by Ed. Stathis Psillos. “Rudolf Carnap’s ‘Theoretical Concepts in Science’.” (2000), pp. 162. Carnap uses Ramsey’s “device”—the Ramsey-sentence of a theory—in order to define analytic truths (in the broad sense) not only for the LO but also LT as well. 9 Carnap, Rudolf. “The Ramsey Sentence.” The Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Basic Books, Inc., (1966), reprinted in Ed. Martin Gardner’s An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Dover Edition, (1974), pp. 252. By “observational language” Carnap is speaking about a language entailing o-terms and o-predicates with elementary logic and mathematics. 6 of the LO, LR has no VT (t-terms and t-predicates). By conceptually engineering LR, Carnap is able to formulate Ramsey-sentences of theories which in turn shows that there can be ways of speaking—which in this case is a very complicated and inconvenient—that entail all observable consequences of theories without the use of VT. What is important is that it is possible to construct a language in which a well-formed sentence (Ramsey-sentence of a theory) captures all observable consequences of that theory. Whether such a construction of a language is practically inconvenient is not relevant. The formulation of a Ramsey-sentence makes it obvious that the question of whether so-and-so t-terms (for example, ‘proton’) or such-and-such tpredicates (for example, ‘charge’ in the theoretical sense) has empirical meaning is no longer problematic. It is not a problem because the question disappears altogether since in LR there is no t-talk to begin with. If Carnap is successful in reinventing a suitable Ramsey device to express the content of scientific theories without resorting to t-discourse, then the Aufbau problem of “surplus meaning” would be no problem. But not only this; for Carnap, it is only through the Ramsey approach that the meaningfulness of t-discourse is supposed to be achieved in a semantical framework where there is a strict distinction between analytic and synthetic truths.10 In other words, his proposed Ramsification of theories solves the problem of defining analytic-truths (in the broad sense) as well. In Carnap’s proposed two-model language of science, a scientific theory consists of all logical consequences of the conjunction of t-postulates and c-postulates. C-postulates result in the derivation of correspondence rules—a name that Carnap prefers over P. W. Bridgman’s 10 Morman, Thomas. “The Structure of Scientific Theories in Logical Empiricism.” Ed. Alan Richardson, Ed. Thomas Uebel. The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism (2007), pp. 153-154. 7 ‘operational rules’ or Norman R. Campbell’s ‘dictionary rules’11—which are mixed sentences entailing both o-and-t-terms. These mixed sentences serve as rules that connect the sentences involving VT with sentences involving VO and provide a partial interpretation to sentences occurring in VT. This is because the sentences of VO are confirmable through experience. The more the correspondence rules, the more the t-discourse is interpreted, but no number of crules is sufficient to result in a complete interpretation of t-discourse. This is why the problem of “surplus meaning” as discussed in the previous section resulted. The logical conjunction of tand-c-postulates in effect entail all observable consequences that a theory could have. Say a theory has n-theoretical terms and m-correspondence postulates, then a theory would simply be expressed as T&C <-> [(T1&T2…Tn-1&Tn) & (C1&C2…Cm-1&Cm)]. Given C-postulates contain tterms and o-terms, such a theory expanded to entail t-classes (for example, a class of all protons) and t-predicates can be represented as follows: Theory = Def. TC(t1,t2,…,tn;o1,o2,...,om) Without realizing Carnap reinvented the Ramsey-approach to scientific theories by proposing existentialized forms of theories.12 To get a Ramsey-sentence of a theory TC, first, we replace all t-terms with corresponding u-variables to get a propositional function (or open ended formula). Secondly, to convert the propositional function containing variables u1,..,un to a 11 Carnap, Rudolf. “Correspondence Rules.” The Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (1966). Reprinted in Ed. Martin Gardner’ An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (1974), pp. 233. 12 “Beobactungssprache und Theoretische Sprache.” (1958). Reprinted with introduction by Ed. Stathis Psillos. “Rudolf Carnap’s ‘Theoretical Concepts in Science’.” (2000), pp. 153. Psillos presents Carnap’s letter to Hemple in which Carnap clearly indicates that it was only after reading Hemple’s ‘The Theoretician’s Dilemma’ that he realized that a Ramsey device was already invented by Ramsey in his ‘Theories’ (1929) paper. 8 sentence having a truth-value, we bind the open-ended formula by adding existential quantifier ∃u1…∃un to the formula. Through this Ramsey device, Carnap is able to provide an incomplete rational reconstruction of TC as a Ramsey-sentence. The Ramsey-sentence of TC is expressible as follows: Ramsey-sentence of a theory TC = Def. RTC: (∃u1)(∃u2)…(∃un)TC(u1,u2,…,un-1,un; o1,o2,…,om) If RTC is true, then it is empirically adequate in that it entails all the observable consequences as TC. The difference being that RTC is an existentialized form of TC. As a result, theoretical terms do not occur in RTC. In place of the t-terms, we now have variables which do not refer to any t-classes, but only asserts that there are classes that satisfy certain descriptions. But, for Carnap, the RTC alone is not a useful explication of TC. Ramsey eliminated t-discourse altogether through his Ramsey process but at the expense of not capturing our preanalytic intuitions of a successful formulation of the analytic/synthetic distinction. In order for Carnap to give a more satisfactory rational construction, he proposed separating the synthetic postulate from its analytic postulate by introducing what has come to be known as a Carnap-sentence of a theory in addition to RTC. The Carnapsentence is an analytic postulate AT which is represented as the conditional RTC -> TC. It is easy to see that AT is devoid of empirical content and true unconditionally since all that it asserts is that “if the Ramsey sentence is true, we must understand the theoretical terms in such a way that the entire theory is true” (Carnap 270)13. As for the synthetic-postulate FT, it must capture all observable consequences of TC. The RTC is a suitable candidate since it 13 “Analyticity in a Theoretical Language.” The Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (1966). Reprinted in Ed. Martin Gardner’ An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (1974). 9 says exactly what TC says without providing any interpretation of t-terms since VT is absent in RTC to begin with. RTC “has factual content simply because it thereby constrains the observable phenomena in definite ways” (Friedman 102)14. A theory, for Carnap, then, is represented as follows: TC ↔ FT & AT ↔ (RTC ) & (RTC->TC) The LR (the Ramsey-extension of observation language) is powerful enough to express FT and AT of TC without naming any t-entities. As a result, Carnap not only does not have to explain the problem of “surplus meaning” but he also separates TC into its synthetic and analytic postulates as Ramsey and Carnap sentences respectively speaking. 4. The Newman Objection: The problem of Triviality or Incoherence Roughly speaking, the Newman problem in effect states that any form of pure epistemic structuralism is either nearly trivial or incoherent. If this is so, then Carnap’s Ramsey proposal of scientific theories may be susceptible to Newman’s objection. This is because Carnap seems to fit a form of epistemic structuralism. His account of a theory TC is structuralist since in the RTC the variables range over logico-mathematical entities. And this is because variables range over a structure of domain that is isomorphic to natural numbers. It is due to such structural isomorphism that we can replace talk of t-entities with “numbers, classes of such, classes of classes” (Carnap 963)15, and so forth. Moreover, his account of a theory TC is also epistemic (as 14 Friedman, Michael. “Carnap’s Philosophical Neutrality Between Realism and Instrumentalism.” Ed. Melanie Frappier, Ed. Derek H. Brown, Ed. Robert DiSalle. Analysis and Interpretation in the Exact Sciences: Essays in Honour of William Demopoulos (2012). 15 “Replies and systematic expositions.” P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (1963). 10 opposed to ontic) since we only have epistemic access of the world up to structure, for Carnap. The Newman’s theorem states the following. Newman’s Theorem: Let S = (U, R1,…,RK) be a structure and V be a set. Suppose that there is an injection p: U -> V. Then, there exists a structure S’ whose domain is V and which has a substructure isomorphic to S.16 Newman’s theorem in effect says that at least all pure epistemic structuralisms that arise from the Ramsey device say nothing whatever beyond the world of observation except imposing a cardinality constraint. This is because all we need RTC to be true is to assign objects of a domain to be the values for the variables that satisfy RTC. And this can be done in an artificial and selfserving manner. The only restriction is that the domain needs to be sufficiently large. This is why RTC is almost trivial. While RTC says that “there are abstracta, classes or properties of this case, that bear certain systematic relations to a large body of observable goings on” (Creath 60)17, the claim follows as a matter of a priori reasoning and a cardinality of the class under question. As Votsis notes, “the mere number of members in an aggregate entails that there are systems of relations definable over those members having a specified structure” (Votsis 881). RTC is trivially satisfied given only a cardinality constrain and yet, RTC is derived from AT the synthetic postulate of TC. This is why the Newman problem makes Carnap’s Ramsey-approach an inadequate representation of TC. But even if we try to avoid the problem of triviality, we do so at the cost of incoherency. The only plausible way to restrict triviality is to specify particular 16 Votsis, Ioannis. “Is Structure Not Enough?” (2003), pp. 881. For definitions that lead to the theorem, refer to the same page. 17 Creath, Richard. “Analyticity in The Theoretical Language: Is a Different Account Really Necessary?” Ed. Richard Creath. Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism (2012). 11 relations that exemplify certain structures. In specifying relations, however, Carnap would no longer be committed to pure epistemic structuralism. This would be inconsistent with Carnap’s neutralist approach. 5. Proposal Sketch: Conceptual Reengineering For Carnap’s Ramsey Approach Given Newman’s objection, I briefly propose that we do not abandon altogether Carnap’s Ramsey-approach to scientific theories. It seems plausible that a suitable conceptual modification to Carnap’s proposed reconstruction of scientific theories could remedy or sidestep altogether the pessimistic force of Newman’s objection with respect to structuralism. We need not abandon altogether any hopes for a neutralist position in the realist/instrumentalist controversy; instead, the Ramsey-way may require conceptual engineering. Given that non-neutralist positions have their own deeply troublesome problems, it is a good and promising decision to search for a reconceptualization of the Ramsey-approach given that “Carnap’s and Ramsey’s reconstructions possess not only internal coherence and elegance, but, more importantly, a degree of philosophical motivation not matched by rival accounts” (Demopoulos 109)18. 6. Conclusion In this paper, I showed that Carnap’s reinvention of the Ramsey-sentence for the purpose of maintaining neutralism in the realism/instrumentalism controversy on scientific theories is subject to the Newman objection. As such, Carnap’s Ramsey-approach to scientific theories requires a conceptual modification in order to avoid incoherence or triviality 18 “On the Rational Reconstruction of our Theoretical Knowledge.” Logicism and Its Philosophical Legacy (2013). I will be attempting a remedy for Newman’s objection for my thesis. 12 conditioned on a cardinality restriction. Such a reconceptualization is well motivated given that the problem of “surplus meaning” and a successful explication of ‘analyticity’ within a theoretical language are also sufficiently forwarded within Carnap’s program of scientific philosophy. Otherwise, the Newman problem is a serious problem for Carnap’s Ramsification of scientific theories. 13 Bibliography Carnap, Rudolf. “Correspondence Rules,” “The Ramsey Sentence,” “Analyticity in an Observation Language,” “Analyticity in a Theoretical Language.” The Philosophical Foundations of Physics: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Basic Books, Inc., (1966), reprinted in Ed. Martin Gardner’ An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Dover Edition, (1974), pp. 232-39, 247-56, 257-64, 265-74. ---------, “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.” Revenue Intern. De Phil. 4, (1950), pp. 20-40; revised and reprinted in Meaning and Necessity, 2nd edition, University of Chicago Press, (1956), Supplementation A). ---------, “Beobactungssprache und Theoretische Sprache.” Dialectica, 12, 236-248; reprinted with introduction by Ed. Stathis Psillos. “Rudolf Carnap’s ‘Theoretical Concepts in Science’.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Vol. 31, No. 1, (2000), pp. 151172. ---------, “Introduction,” “Logical Analysis of Confirmation and Testing.” Testability and Meaning. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 3, Number 4, (1936), pp. 420-448. ---------, “Replies and systematic expositions.” P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. LaSalle, IL: Open Court, (1963), pp. 859–1013. Creath, Richard. “Analyticity in The Theoretical Language: Is a Different Account Really Necessary?” Ed. Richard Creath. Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, Vol. 16, (2012), pp. 57-66. Demopoulos, William. “On the Rational Reconstruction of our Theoretical Knowledge.” Logicism and Its Philosophical Legacy. Cambridge University Press, (2013), pp. 108-139. Friedman, Michael. “Carnap’s Philosophical Neutrality Between Realism and Instrumentalism.” Ed. Melanie Frappier, Ed. Derek H. Brown, Ed. Robert DiSalle. Analysis and Interpretation in the Exact Sciences: Essays in Honour of William Demopoulos. Springer, Vol. 78, (2012), pp. 95-114. 14 ---------, “Carnap’s Aufbau Reconsidered.” Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge University Press, (1999), pp. 89-114. Leitgeb, Hannes. “New Life for Carnap’s Aufbau.” Synthese, Vol. 180, number 2, (2011), pp. 265-299. URL = <NewLifeLink> Morman, Thomas. “The Structure of Scientific Theories in Logical Empiricism.” Ed. Alan Richardson, Ed. Thomas Uebel. The Cambridge Companion to Logical Empiricism. Cambridge University Press, (2007), pp. 136-164. Pincock, Christopher. “Carnap, Russell, and the External World.” Ed. Richard Creath, Ed. Michael Friedman, Ed. The Cambridge Companion to Carnap. Cambridge University Press, (2007), pp. 106-128. Psillos, Stathis. “Carnap’s Neutralism.” Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. Routledge, (1999), pp. 38-67. Quine, Willard Van. “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, (1951), pp. 20-43. Reprinted in W.V.O. Quine, From a Logical Point of View (Harvard University Press, 1953; second, revised, edition 1961), with the following alterations: "The version printed here diverges from the original in footnotes and in other minor respects: §§1 and 6 have been abridged where they encroach on the preceding essay ["On What There Is"], and §§3-4 have been expanded at points." URL = <For the link, click here>. Votsis, Ioannis. “Is Structure Not Enough?” Philosophy of Science, Vol. 70, (2003), pp. 879-890.
© Copyright 2025