The division of the mind: Paradoxes and puzzles Vasco Correia Institute for the Philosophy of Language Universidade Nova de Lisboa vasco_saragoca@hotmail.com 1. Introduction The hypothesis that the mind is in some way divided is often put forward in an attempt to make sense of irrationality, whether in the cognitive sphere (delusional beliefs) or in the practical sphere (incontinent actions). In essence, the “divisionist” argument states that one cannot understand irrational actions and beliefs without assuming that the mind is composed of different sub-systems. Donald Davidson, for example, explicitly endorses this methodological assumption: “I have urged in several papers that it is only by postulating a kind of compartmentalization of the mind that we can understand, and begin to explain, irrationality”1. Likewise, Aristotle introduces the distinction between the “rational” and the “irrational” part of the soul in reference to the case of akratic action (or “lack of selfcontrol”), in which the agent deliberately acts against his best judgment2. And it is also the problem of irrationality that leads Plato to argue in The Republic that there are three components of the soul (nous, thumos and epithumia). Irrational action, he argues, would result of a conflict between those components. Plato evokes the case of Leontios, a man who was unable to resist the temptation of staring at a bunch of dead bodies, despite deeming such a voyeurism morally wrong. The puzzling thing about this sort of behavior is that the agent seemingly knows it is in his best interest to perform the course of action A, all things considered, and nevertheless ends up doing B. In the philosophical tradition, the gist of the question has always been the very possibility of such attitudes. Can one see the best option, and approve of it, and nonetheless, in full awareness, chose the worst option? How is that possible? Although a number of philosophers deny the possibility of akrasia thus described, the proponents of the divisionist hypothesis argue that it is indeed possible to act contrary to one’s best judgment, insofar as there are different instances operating in the mind. In the case of Leontios, for example, it all seemed to happen as though a part of him wanted to stare at the gruesome scene, while another part of him utterly repudiated such an attitude3. Many authors make a similar claim with regard to specific cases of cognitive irrationality, such as self-deception, making the case that this type of phenomenon also 1 Davidson, “Incoherence and Irrationality”, Dialectica, vol. 39 (nº 4), p. 353. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1102b. 3 Hence Plato’s metaphor in the Phaedrus depicting the psyche as a “composite pair of winged horses (…) one of them noble and of noble breed and the other ignoble and of ignoble breed”, constantly torn between the impulses of desire and the recommendations of reason (Plato, Phaedrus, transl. B. Jowett, 245ab). 2 requires some sort of differentiation within the mind1. In their view, there is a formal analogy between self-deception and akrasia insofar as both phenomena seem to imply some degree of inconsistency between the agent’s attitudes: the akratic agent is someone who believes that A is the better option and nonetheless decides to do B; and the self-deceiver, likewise, is someone who believes that p is the most likely hypothesis and nonetheless decides to believe that not-p. After all, if the self-deceiver did not initially hold the unwelcome belief that p, he would have no reason to make the effort of embracing the opposite belief. For example, if John did not know “deep inside him” that he is an alcoholic, he wouldn’t go to great pains to persuade himself that he doesn’t have a problem with alcohol. To that extent, as Davidson points out, it would seem as though the initial belief that p, in concert with the desire that not-p, causally sustains the contradictory belief that not-p: “Self-deception is notoriously troublesome, since in some of its manifestations it seems to require us not only to say that someone beliefs both a certain proposition and its negation, but also to hold that the one belief sustains the other”2. According to the so-called “intentionalist” account of self-deception, at least, the self-deceiver must hold two contradictory beliefs simultaneously; he must belief that p is true, while also believing that p is false. And this is precisely why the divisionist hypothesis is so appealing to many authors, since it accounts for irrationality in terms of inner inconsistency without raising the paradox of contradictory attitudes coexisting in the same mind. Assuming that the mind is indeed divided, it may well happen that conflicts and even contradictions arise between the different sub-systems. Even at a cognitive level, it doesn’t appear paradoxical to hold two contradictory beliefs simultaneously, provided that the beliefs in question belong to different parts of the mind. In this sense, divisionists seem able to avoid what Alfred Mele calls the “doxastic paradox” of self-deception, that is to say the fact that the self-deceiver appears to believe that p and that not-p simultaneously3. According to Robert Audi, in particular, this is possible because the contradictory beliefs coexist at different levels: the subject believes that p at a conscious level, whereas he “unconsciously knows that not-p (or has reason to believe, and unconsciously and truly believes, non-p”4. To that extent, it seems possible not only that the subject holds the contradictory beliefs simultaneously, but also that he remains unaware of the contradiction (the two beliefs “failing to clash”, so to speak). There are nevertheless two crucial difficulties which seem to undermine the divisionist postulate. The first was pointed out by Sartre in his famous analysis of the mauvaise foi (or self-deception) and concerns primarily Freudian-like accounts of the divided mind. Sartre’s argument is presented as a dilemma, known as the “paradox of repression”, and questions the idea that a part of the mind (supposedly unconscious) could somehow perform the complex task of preventing another part of the mind from contemplating harmful representations. The second difficulty, on the other hand, concerns all sorts of divisionism, Freudian-like or not. It is commonly referred to as the “homunculus fallacy” and was initially stressed by Wittgenstein, who argued that the suggestion that there are relatively autonomous sub-systems coexisting in the mind utterly compromises the very notion of personal identity. 1 In particular, Donald Davidson, Robert Audi, David Pears, Herbert Fingarette and Sebastian Gardner. Davidson, “Deception and Division”, in Le Pore and McLaughlin, Actions and Events. Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1985, p. 138. 3 Mele, Alfred, “Two Paradoxes of Self-Deception”, in Self-Deception and Paradoxes of Rationality, ed. by Dupuy, Stanford: CSLI Publications, 1998, p. 38. 4 Audi, “Self-Deception, Action and Will”, Erkenntnis, 18, 1982, p. 137. 2 In this paper I shall examine some of the most influent versions of the divisionist account, namely the models developed by Freud, Fingarette, Pears and Davidson. I argue that (1) each of these accounts leads to a specific paradox or set of paradoxes, and also that (2) the divisionist hypothesis is not necessary to explain ordinary cases of irrationality, such as self-deception, denial, rationalization, wishful thinking, and the like. This is not to say that it is impossible for our minds to suffer any sort of division – as it undoubtedly appears to happen in pathological cases of mental dissociation - but simply that one does not need to assume such divisions to explain ordinary cases of irrationality. My view is that most cases of irrationality, whether practical or cognitive, stem from the influence that desires and other emotions are liable to exert upon our cognitive faculties, and thereby upon our judgments. If this hypothesis is correct, irrational thought and irrational behavior are typically caused by a conflict between individual mental states (for example, a conflict between a desire and a belief), and not from a conflict between differentiated parts of the mind. 2. The paradoxes of the Freudian account It is worth beginning by examining Freud’s model of divisionism, since it admittedly inspired Fingarette’s, Pears’ and Davidson’s recent versions of divisionism. As Freud often stresses, the cornerstone of psychoanalytic theory is the claim that a significant number of our representations remain unconscious or repressed, forming what he initially calls the Unconscious (das Unbewusste) and later the Id: “the division of mental life into what is conscious and what is unconscious is the fundamental premise on which psycho-analysis is based”1. But he also specifies that unconscious contents remain excluded from the consciousness, not because our consciousness accidentally neglects to contemplate them, but because they cannot become conscious, insofar as a given strength represses them: “Analysis of these examples of forgetting reveals that the motive of forgetting is always an unwillingness to recall something which may evoke painful feelings”2. In fact, the process of repression needs to be understood in light of the fundamental principles that rule the psychic apparatus, and particularly the so-called “pleasure principle”, which implies that the psyche spontaneously seeks pleasure and avoids pain (caeteris paribus). Thus, a representation is repressed either because it is deemed too painful to be made conscious or because it constitutes a threat, directly or indirectly, to the equilibrium of the psychic apparatus as a whole. In L’être et le néant Sartre famously argues that the Freudian account is intrinsically paradoxical. The nerve of Sartre’s argument is that the so-called Unconscious would have to behave as a sort of “second consciousness” to be able to repress harmful thoughts3. After all, Sartre observes, in order to withhold dangerous information from the consciousness, the Unconscious would have to perform the highly complex task of assessing the potential impact of each given representation in the economy of the psyche. Yet, such a task could not be achieved successfully without the unconscious being aware of the representations in question, for otherwise it would lack the means to decide which information is suitable to be made conscious, and which 1 Freud, The Ego and the Id (1923), trans. Joan Riviere, Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-analysis, London, 1927, p. 19. 2 Freud, Psychopathology of Everyday Life (1901), trans. A. Brill, T. Fisher Unwin, London, 1914, Chap. 12, p. 332. 3 Sartre, L’être et le néant, Gallimard, 1943, I, ch. 2. information needs to be repressed. But if that were indeed the case, the unconscious would have to know the negative representations in order not to know them, which seems rather paradoxical1. The second problem with Freud’s account is that it challenges the concept of personal identity, since it attributes propositional attitudes such as beliefs, desires, representations, memories and emotions to mere parts of the mind, despite the fact that attitudes of this sort only seem appropriate to describe the person as a whole (the individual, strictly speaking). As Wittgenstein points out, “only of a human being and what resembles (behaves like) a living human being can one say: it has sensations; it sees, is blind; hears, is deaf; is conscious or unconscious”2. Freud’s description of the mind’s components often falls into what Anthony Kenny calls the “homunculus fallacy”, in other words the tendency to describe the alleged parts of the mind as though they were different persons within the person. In The Ego and the Id, in particular, Freud develops an anthropomorphic model which depicts the ego, the super-ego and the id as different “homunculi” coexisting and competing in accordance with their specific set of demands. Regarding the ego, for example, he writes that “we can see [it] as a poor little creature subjected to servitude in three different ways, and threatened in consequence by three different dangers – one posed by the external world, one by the libido of the id, and one by the harshness of the super-ego”3. Likewise, in An Outline of Psychoanalysis Freud goes as far as to suggest that the psychoanalyst ought to make an alliance with one of the mind’s components, namely the ego, in an attempt to protect it from the demands set by its two rivals: “The analytic physician and the patient’s weakened ego, basing themselves on the real external world, have to band themselves together into a party against the enemies, the instinctual demands of the id and the conscientious demands of the super-ego. We form a pact with each other”4. But this raises very acutely the problem of personal identity, given that the components of the psyche do not seem to have much in common. Under such a description, in effect, one cannot help but wonder what sort of principle would be able to ensure the overall unity of the several sub-systems. Sartre also stresses this point: “By rejecting the conscious unity of the psyche, Freud is obliged to presuppose everywhere a magic unity linking distant phenomena across obstacles”5. Irvin Thalberg makes a similar objection by raising the “who?” questions regarding the alleged constituents of the psychic apparatus: “Is our ego awake or asleep when we sleep?”; “Which ‘self’ does my ego have the duty of protecting?”; “Whom does my super-ego watch when it engages in ‘self-observation’ – me, my ego, itself?”; “Whose enjoyment do [my instincts] ‘strive’ for?”; and “Whose interests is the ego trying to protect in its repressions?”6. Far from solving this serious difficulty, Freud only seems to aggravate it in his later writings, bringing forward the hypothesis of a socalled “splitting of the Ego” (Ichspaltung). In the posthumous text “The splitting of the Ego in the process of defense”, remarkably, he claims that the ego itself is liable to 1 In a recent paper, Simon Boag argued that the resolution of this paradox hinges upon the recognition that the process of repression inhibits knowledge of knowing the repressed (Boag, “Realism, SelfDeception and the Logical Paradox of Repression”, Theory and Psychology, 17 (3), 2007, p. 421-447). The problem with this solution, however, is that a third degree knowledge would then be required to determine which knowledge of the knowledge is to be inhibited, and which is not. 2 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 1953, § 281. 3 Freud, The Ego and the Id (1923), Penguin classics, London, 2003, p. 146. 4 Freud, An outline of Psycho-analysis (1940), The Standard Edition, Vintage, London, 2001, p. 173. 5 Sartre, id., p. 89. 6 Thalberg, “Freud’s Anatomies of the Self”, in R. Wollheim, and J. Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge University Press, 1984, pp. 253-254. suffer an inner division. When the conflict between the ego’s desires and what reality demands becomes unbearable, Freud writes, “The two contrary reactions to the conflict persist as the center-point of a splitting of the ego (…) The synthetic function of the ego, though it is of such extraordinary importance, is subject to particular conditions and is liable to a whole number of disturbances”1. Although Freud initially confines this hypothesis to the specific cases of fetishism and psychosis, he later extends it to neurosis in general2. But, of course, if the components of the mind may themselves be sub-divided into sub-constituents, the paradoxes of divisionism become all the more difficult to surmount. 3. Fingarette: “ego” and “counter-ego” In spite of these difficulties, Herbert Fingarette’s analysis takes up Freud’s idea of a splitting of the ego. Nevertheless, he gives it an ingenious twist by suggesting that the ego’s inner conflicts lead to the formation of what he calls a “counter-ego”. According to the author, this instance is formed during the emergence of the person’s self and coexists with the ego in the mind throughout live: “The defensive outcome, then, is to establish what we may call a counter-ego nucleus, this nucleus being the structural aspect of counter-cathexis”3. Aware of the dilemmas that Freud’s theory seems to face, Fingarette explains that “such paradoxes as this arise because both earlier and later versions [of Freud’s theory] are parallel in insisting correctly on the fact that there is a split in the psyche, but fail in defining the nature of the split adequately”4. The adequate adequate way to define de nature of the split, in the author’s view, would be to suggest that every ego is essentially divided (and not just the neurotic or the psychotic ego), and also that the upshot of such a division is the formation of two basic sub-systems, the ego and the counter-ego. Furthermore, Fingarette contends that the origin of such a split is not the process of repression, but a process of “disavowal” through which the counter-ego is split off from the ego. He illustrates this process by evoking the example of a man who resents his employer’s attitude toward him, but is unable to accept (or avow) his own resentment because he considers it immoral to feel such an anger toward someone else. As a result, Fingarette argues, the subject refuses to identify himself to the attitude in question and claims: “It is not ‘I’ who am angry; from henceforth I will dissociate myself from it; it is repugnant to me”5. The process of split off would begin at an early age, through the constraints of education and social interactions. Negative feelings such as shame and guilt, in particular, would play an important role in causing the person to “disavow” certain emotions and desires, progressively inducing the creation and development of a counter-ego nucleus in the mind. 1 Freud, “The splitting of the Ego in the process of defense”, The Standard Edition, Vintage, The Hogarth Press, London, vol. XXIII, p. 276. 2 Cf. Freud, Outline of Psycho-Analysis, The Standard Edition, Vintage, The Hogarth Press, London, vol. XXIII, p. 202: “The view which postulates that in all psychoses there is a splitting of the ego could not call for so much notice if it did not turn out to apply to other states more like the neuroses and, finally, to the neuroses themselves”. 3 Fingarette, “Self-deception and the splitting of the ego”, in R., Wollheim, & J., Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge University Press, 1984, p. 224. 4 Fingarette, id., p. 223. 5 Fingarette, id., p. 218. The advantage of Fingarette’s account is that it seems to avoid the paradox of repression, given that the phenomenon of disavowal, unlike Freud’s mechanism of repression, is both a conscious and deliberate act performed by the person’s Ego: “the defensive process is a splitting of the ego which is not something that ‘happens’ to the ego but something the ego does, a motivated strategy”1. There is however a fundamental dilemma in Fingarette’s account: assuming that the counter-ego is not repressed (nor unconscious) but merely “split-off” from the ego, it follows that the same consciousness must serve the purposes both of the ego and of the counter-ego. But how could the Ego and the counter-ego remain effectively dissociated if they share the exact same consciousness? Here lies the paradox: on the one hand, the subject’s consciousness is meant to deny the set of beliefs and emotions which seem unacceptable to the ego; but on the other hand, as part of the counter-ego, the consciousness must be aware of such beliefs and emotions. In the previous case, for example, the subject has to be aware of his anger toward his boss, for otherwise he wouldn’t bother to deny it. But if the subject’s ego knows about the unacceptable emotions, how can it not recognize them as its own? And what sense does it make to say that the subject’s consciousness acknowledges certain attitudes as a counter-ego, but not as an ego? An additional problem with Fingarette’s account lies in the assumption that people are capable of disavowing inconvenient realities both consciously and voluntarily. This philosophical hypothesis, known as doxastic voluntarism, is in fact ruled out as a psychological impossibility by most philosophers and psychologists, who argue that no one seems to be able to decide at will, hic et nunc, what to believe or not2. As Jonathan Bennett points out, although it may not be conceptually impossible to cause oneself to believe something at will, it seems de facto impossible to achieve such a task: “There could be simpler, quicker, more reliable means for causing beliefs in people without giving them evidence. I passionately want to spend the evening in a state of confidence that the whether will be fine tomorrow (I have my practical reasons), so I give myself the thought of tomorrow’s whether being fine while snapping my fingers in a certain way, and sure enough I end up convinced that the whether will be fine tomorrow. We have no such fast, reliable techniques for producing belief without evidence, but they are not conceptually ruled out”.3 Finally, one could also question the very existence of a so-called “counter-ego”, much like Freud’s opponents have questioned the existence of an unconscious. Even assuming that the process of denial may occur intentionally, it seems indeed doubtful that it should result in the formation of a counter-ego which most of us would be unaware of. 4. Pears: the rival “centers of agency” In a sense, one could describe David Pears’ version of divisionism as a compromise between Freud’s founder model and Fingarette’s sophisticated account. On the one 1 Fingarette, id., p. 224. See for example Pascal Engel, “Volitionism and Voluntarism About Belief”, in A. Meijers (ed.), Belief, Cognition and the Will, Tilburg University Press, 1999. 3 Bennett, “Why is Believing Involuntary ?”, Analysis, 50, 1990, p. 96. 2 hand, Pears agrees with Fingarette to say that the divided mind is essentially composed of two sub-systems, instead of the three Freud describes, which he generically refers to as the “main” and the “secondary” sub-system. But one the other hand, Pears adopts the Freudian assumption that one of those sub-systems must remain unconscious: “There is then one centre of activity in the subject’s contemporary consciousness and another in the reservoir (…) We have to suppose that each of these two centres includes any information needed to give its desire a line of action (…) This extremely economic hypothesis is based on Freud’s fundamental concept of a boundary dividing the conscious from the preconscious and the unconscious”1. Pears suggests that this is “the most economical form of the hypothesis of the divided mind”2, not only because it refrains from engaging in an anthropomorphic description of the mind’s sub-systems, but also because it does not postulate that such a division is an essential feature which characterizes each and every mind. According to Pears, we only need to assume that the mind suffers this kind of differentiation in the case of subjects who are prone to some degree of irrationality, whether cognitive or practical. In principle, the cause of the division is the emergence of a strong desire which turns out to be incompatible with the subject’s predominant preferences. For example, the desire of having an extra-marital affair with an attractive person is of course incompatible with the aspiration to remain a faithful partner and a moral person3. If strong enough, the desire in question may eventually form what Pears calls a “rival centre of agency”, which is able to compete with the main sub-system and liable to induce irrational behavior and irrational thinking. The interest of Pears’ account is that it avoids the homunculus fallacy, given that the secondary sub-system of the mind is described as a purely functional entity. To begin with, it is not an essential feature of the mind, but a characteristic which only applies to irrational minds; secondly, it is not defined idiosyncratically, given that any type of desires could in principle characterize the rebellious sub-system; and finally, for that very reason, it may actually differ from one person to the other (unlike Freudian sub-systems, which are supposedly universal). Nevertheless, Pears’ model seems unable to avoid the paradox of repression. After all, how could the secondary sub-system, which is unconscious, be able to assess the impact of each mental state on the psychic apparatus? It seems indeed difficult to conceive that an unconscious instance should possess the awareness and the discernment required to predict the positive or negative impact of every belief, every desire and every representation upon the subject’s mental equilibrium. Aware of this difficulty, Pears argues that the act through which the mind excludes a given content from consciousness is not only unconscious but also “self-reflective”: “The only possible reply is that the suppression of the consciousness that normally accompanies a particular type of mental event may itself be unconscious without having succumbed to a previous act of suppression. To put the point in another way, suppression can be selfreflective”4. 1 Pears, “Motivated irrationality, Freudian theory and cognitive dissonance”, in Wollheim R. and Hopkins J., (eds.) Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982, p. 269. 2 Pears. Id., p. 268. 3 It is worth noting, however, that the rebellious desire could in principle be of any type: not just a sexual drive, as in many of Freud’s analysis, but also professional ambition, desire of fame and glory, desire to get rich, and so forth, depending on the type of preferences and moral values which are specific to the subject. 4 Pears, id., p. 275. Ingenious as it may sound, Pears’ solution seems insufficient to neutralize Sartre’s criticism, for even if we accept the idea that there are self-reflective acts of repression, remains to be answered the question of how exactly such mental acts are able to perform the elaborated task of separating the wheat from the chaff, so to speak, sorting out what might be beneficial and what might be harmful for the mind. As Mark Johnston rightly points out, this would imply that an unconscious sub-system of the mind should be able to manipulate the main system in the best interest of the mind as a whole: “The question arises how the protective system could do all this without being conscious of (introspecting) its own operations. After all, it has to compare the outcome it is producing with the outcome it aimed for and act or cease to act accordingly. Any consciousness by the protective system of its own operation is “buried alive”, i.e., is not acceptable to the consciousness of the main system”1. An additional problem is that Pears’ definition of the secondary sub-system remains somewhat vague. He writes that, for the mind to be divided, “there must be two conflicting desires which set up rival centers of activity”2, but neglects to specify which other conditions must be combined for the division to occur. In particular, the reader is left wondering whether there are as many secondary sub-systems of the mind as there are strong conflicts between desires. In the book Irrationality Alfred Mele stresses this point with an amusing analogy: “Explaining doxastic irrationality in Pears’s fashion is rather like explaining how a football team held another scoreless by saying that the former strategically rendered all of the latter’s scoring attempts ineffective. The football fan wants much more than this. He wants to know how team A rendered team B’s attempts ineffective”3. 5. Davidson: the mind’s “compartments” Although Donald Davidson extensively acknowledges to what extent his account of irrationality is inspired by Freud’s analysis, the divisionist hypothesis he puts forward is actually much weaker that Freud’s, and arguably even more minimal than Pears’. To begin with, he doesn’t assume that there is such a thing as an unconscious part of the mind which the subject’s consciousness would be unable to access. He doesn’t go as far as to deny the existence of an Unconscious, but clearly states that we do not need to presuppose the existence of contents inaccessible to the consciousness to be able to make sense of irrationality. All we need to presuppose, he argues, is that there are different “territories” or “compartments” in the mind which the consciousness cannot survey simultaneously. In addition, while Pears and Fingarette suggest that the secondary sub-system emerges in the mind as an organized centre of action, competing with the main system and aiming at distinct goals, Davidson refuses to speculate about that aspect; and, to that extent, seems to avoid the homunculus fallacy. All that is required, Davidson suggests, 1 Johnston, “Self-Deception and the Nature of Mind”, in Rorty and McLaughlin (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception, Berkeley, L.A., London, University of California Press, 1982, p. 82. 2 Pears, id., p. 268. 3 Mele, Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception and Self-Control, N.Y., Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1987, p. 143. is that “within each [department of mind] there is a fair degree of consistency, and where one element can operate on another in the modality of non-rational causality”1. Thus, if an agent holds contradictory beliefs, as in the case of self-deception, one should assume that there is a subsystem of mental states consistent with the belief that p, and another sub-system of mental states consistent with the belief that not-p. More specifically, Davidson suggests that the partition of the mind occurs whenever a nonrational causality arises, i.e. whenever a mental state A causes a mental state B without being a (good) reason for B. For example, Jack’s belief that Jane is in love with him is irrational in case it’s caused by his feelings for Jane (instead of objective information), to the extent that his desire to be loved by Jane is surely not a good reason to believe that Jane is in love with him. If Jack’s irrational belief stems from a genuine process of self-deception, and not from sheer wishful thinking, this would mean that a compartment of his mind believes that Jane is in love with him, while another compartment of his mind believes the opposite. And in a sense, Davidson explains, it’s precisely because Jack believes that Jane probably doesn’t love him (and because he cannot bear that reality) that he is motivated to embrace the belief that she does - the former belief causally inducing the later. Despite the advantages of Davidson’s account relatively to other divisionist models, it seems to encounter a new set of problems. The first difficulty is that it undermines Davidson’s own holistic theory of mind, which contends that an individual mental state can only be understood in light of the whole set of attitudes constitutive of the subject’s mind, and that there must be a large degree of consistency between those attitudes. Davidson highlights himself the difficulty: “There is no question but that the precept of unavoidable charity in interpretation is opposed to the partitioning of the mind. For the point of partitioning was to allow inconsistent or conflicting beliefs and desires and feelings to exist in the same mind, while the basic methodology of all interpretation tells us that inconsistency breeds unintelligibility”2. A second insufficiency lies in the fact that Davidson’s description of the mind’s sub-systems remains too vague. As Pears points out, “[t]he drawing of a fault-line through a point at which internal irrationality occurs is only the beginning of the theory, and it is not enough to identify a sub-system”3. As a matter of fact, Davidson states that whenever irrational causality occurs in the mind one must assume that a correlative partition is consumed; but he doesn’t specify how that partition comes about, or the terms in which the sub-systems co-exist and interact. Besides, as Pascal Engel rightly suggests, the vagueness of Davidson’s analysis extends to the very dynamic underlying the mind’s alleged differentiation: “[Davidson’s model] would need the equivalent of what Freud calls the dynamic aspect of the unconscious to account for the interactions between the sub-systems”4. In other words, what Davidson’s model seems to lack is a descriptive account of irrationality, rather than a merely normative one. And finally, many authors have questioned Davidson’s claim that ordinary cases of irrationality, such as weakness of will and self-deception, necessarily involve some sort of inconsistency between the agent’s mental attitudes (which, in turn, would justify 1 Davidson, “Paradoxes of Irrationality”, in R., Wollheim, & J., Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982, p. 182. 2 Davidson, id., p. 184. 3 David Pears, “Self-Deceptive Belief Formation”, 1991, Synthese, vol. 89, nº 3, p. 395. 4 Engel, Avant propos à Davidson, Paradoxes de l’irrationalité, p. 16. the claim that such cases necessarily presuppose a partition of the mind). With regard to weakness of will, authors such as George Ainslie and Jon Elster convincingly argue that one needs not to conceive the phenomenon as the result of an action contrary to the agent’s own judgment, as if the action and the intention to act were strictly opposed. More plausibly, what seems to happen when an agent yields to temptation in spite of a previous decision is that he revises his initial judgment in a sudden and ill-considered fashion under the pressure of an urging desire. Thus, for example, my strong desire to eat a dessert is liable to affect my judgment temporarily and lead me insidiously to revise the decision to loose weight. Even if, all things considered, the option of loosing weight might be the one which maximizes my well-being, the craving for a more immediate reward induces a biased perception of my preferences and causes me to believe, for a short and decisive instant, that it is preferable to eat the dessert. Ainslie calls this cognitive effect “hyperbolic discounting bias”, which he defines as a sort of myopia regarding preferences over time: caeteris paribus, people tend to overrate the value of immediate rewards and to underrate the value of future rewards1. In light of this hypothesis, the agent who chooses to go on a diet and eventually fails to act accordingly does not act against his own judgment, strictly speaking, for at the time he eats the dessert his (biased) judgment assesses that option as being preferable. In this sense, there is no inner inconsistency in the agent’s mind (no simultaneously contradictory intentions to act), but simply an evolution in time of the agent’s preferences; in other words, a revised decision, however irrational and temporary it may turn out to be. Now, the consequence of this analysis is that divisionism is not required as a presupposition to understand irrational action, given that a diachronic inconsistence of preferences does not raise the paradox of contradictory attitudes. Likewise, several philosophers and psychologists have argued that selfdeception does not imply neither some sort of inner inconsistency in the subject’s mind. Alfred Mele and Ariela Lazar, in particular, have argued that self-deception does not entail the subject holding two contradictory beliefs at the same time, but simply a hiatus between what the available evidence clearly suggests, on the one hand, and what the subject is lead to believe, on the other hand. In their view, the self-deceived subject does not initially know the true proposition that p and at some point decides to believe the false proposition that not-p. Instead, what happens is that the subject’s judgment is biased by some desire (or other emotion) which induces a distorted perception of the reality. If Jack believes that Jane is in love with him in the teeth of evidence, for example, the problem is not that Jack intentionally decides to believe what seems more convenient, as Davidson suggests, but rather that his feelings for Jane surreptitiously bias his interpretation of her attitudes toward him. A sheer sign of friendship will then appear as an unquestionable proof of love. But, again, if there are no contradictory beliefs in the agent’s mind, if the irrational belief simply results from a biased perception of the reality, there is no compelling reason to assume that his mind is divided and that one part of the mind is aware of the truth while the other one is being deceived. Furthermore, as Mele observes, it would be paradoxical to suggest that one part of the mind is able to employ a deceptive strategy upon the other, given that a “potential self-deceiver’s knowledge of his intention and strategy would seem typically to render them ineffective”2. 1 2 See Ainslie, Break-Down of Will, Cambridge University Press, 2001. Mele, Irrationality, op. cit., p. 121. 6. Conclusion: toward a unitary solution In essence, our critical analysis brings about two significant conclusions. First, (i) that each version of the divisionist account appears to lead to a certain number of paradoxes. This is not to say that the divisionist view is intrinsically paradoxical, but simply that, to my knowledge, no consistent model of divisionism has been developed so far. Second, and perhaps more importantly, it would seem (ii) that it is not necessary to postulate the division of the mind in order to account for the vast majority of cases of irrationality. As we have seen in the last section of this paper, the vast majority of cases of cognitive and practical irrationality can be accounted for in unitary terms, without appealing to the divionist postulate. Crucially, my claim is that both irrational behavior and irrational reasoning can be explained as the result of a conflict between individual mental states, and not from a conflict between differentiated parts of the mind. We have seen it regarding cognitive cases of irrationality, such as self-deception, denial, rationalization, wishful thinking, and the like, which seemingly stem from the influence our desires and emotions are liable to exert upon our judgments. And we have seen it regarding practical cases of irrationality, and particularly akrasia (or weakness of will), which can also be understood as the result of a biased judgment, given that the very same phenomenon of motivated irrationality is susceptible to affect the evaluative judgments upon which we base our choices. Here too, it’s simply an individual mental state, generally a desire, that induces an irrational assessment of the feasible options and subsequently an irrational action. Having said that, the fact that the hypothesis of mental partitioning is not required to explain ordinary cases of irrationality does not mean that it does not apply to extreme cases of irrationality, and particularly to pathological cases of “dissociative identity” (DSM IV) or “multiple personality disorder” (ICD 10). This is the reason why it would be wrong to rule out the idea that the mind may be divided as a paradox per se. Instead, it seems fair to suggest that divisionism remains a puzzle to be solved. From that perspective, it would be interesting to examine what exactly makes the difference between “normal” and “pathological” cases of irrationality with regard to identity disorders. References BIRD, Alexander, 1994 – “Rationality and the Structure of Self-Deception”, European Review of Philosophy, 1. pp. 19-37. BOAG, Simon, 2007 – “Realism, Self-Deception and the Logical Paradox of Repression”, Theory and Psychology, 17 (3), pp. 421-447. BOUVERESSE, J., 1991 – Philosophie, mythologie et pseudo-science, Combas: L’éclat. DAVIDSON, Donald, 1982 – “Paradoxes of Irrationality”, in R., Wollheim, & J., Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. - 1985a – “Deception and Division”, in Actions and Events, E. Lepore and B. McLaughlin (eds.), New York: Basil Blackwell. - 1985b, “Incoherence and Irrationality”, Dialectica, vol. 39 (nº 4), p. 345-353. - 1998 – “Who is Fooled?”, in Dupuy, Self-Deception and Paradoxes of Rationality, Stanford: CSLI Publications, p. 1-19. ELSTER (ed.), 1985 - The Multiple Self, Cambridge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. FINGARETTE, Herbert, 1984 - “Self-deception and the splitting of the ego”, in R., Wollheim, & J., Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. FREUD, Sigmund, Beyond the Pleasure Principle (1920), tranl. J. Reddick, Penguin classics, London, 2003. - The Ego and the Id (1923), transl. J. Reddick, Penguin classics, London, 2003. - Freud, An outline of Psycho-analysis (1940), The Standard Edition, Vintage, London, 2001, p. 173. - “Splitting of the Ego in the Process of Defense”, 1938, transl. James Strachey, The Standard Edition, vol. XXIII, Vintage, London, 1964, pp. 271-279. - JOHNSTON, Mark, 1989 - “Self-Deception and the Nature of Mind”, in Rorty and McLaughlin (eds.), Perspectives on Self-Deception, Berkeley, L.A., London: University of California Press, pp. 63-91. - KENNY, Anthony, 1984 – “The Homunculus Fallacy”, in The Legacy of Wittgenstein, Oxford: Blackwell, chap. 9, pp. 125-136.~ MELE, Alfred, 1987a – Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self-Deception and Self-Control, N.Y., Oxford: Oxford University Press. - 1998 - « Two Paradoxes of Self-Deception », in J.P. Dupuy, Self-Deception and Paradoxes of Rationality, CSLI Publications, Stanford, California, p. 37-58. - PEARS, David, 1982 – “Motivated irrationality, Freudian theory and cognitive dissonance”, in Wollheim R. and Hopkins J., (eds.) Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 279-288. - 1984 - Motivated irrationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. - SARTRE, Jean-Paul, 1943 - L’être et le néant, Paris: Seuil. - TALBOTT, William, 1995 - « Intentional Self-deception in a Single, Coherent Self », Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55, nº 1, pp. 27-74. - THALBERG, Irvin, 1984 - “Freud’s Anatomies of the Self”, in R., Wollheim, & J., Hopkins, (eds.), Philosophical Essays on Freud, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. - WITTGENSTEIN, Ludwig, 1953 – Philosophical Investigations, transl. Anscombe, Oxford: Blackwell.
© Copyright 2024