Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Editors’ welcome It is with great excitement that this year’s commi ee introduces to you the first print issue of the Queen Mary Undergraduate History Journal for the 2014/15 academic year. Established in 2011, the History Journal con nues to publish brilliant essays from undergraduates month a er month, year a er year; a fact that pays testament to the high standard of work expected by the School of History at Queen Mary, and of which our undergraduates are capable. As the essay tles in this very issue suggest, the School of History boasts a wide variety of interes ng modules taught by experts at the cu ng edge of research in their specialist fields. We would like to take this this opportunity to recognise recent milestones in the life of the History Journal. The History Journal has now adopted a Queen Mary email domain: historyjournal@qmul.ac.uk -please send any future essay submissions or enquires to this address. Secondly, the History Journal now has a QMPLUS module, which all full- me History undergraduates have been granted automa c access to. For this achievement, we would like to thank Dr. Chris Sparks. The Queen Mary History Journal Blog has now been launched and can be found at: h ps://queenmaryhistoryjournal.wordpress.com/. We hope that this ini a ve will provide students with a pla orm to discuss their opinions both formally and informally, with the added bonus of a comment sec on to generate further discussion. You can also find the blog on Twi er @QMHJBlog and Facebook under ‘Queen Mary History Journal Blog’. Should you have pieces that you wish to submit or any general enquiries, do not hesitate to email us. December and January saw an unprecedented amount of work submi ed to the History Journal, which was given due considera on and edited where appropriate. We would like to thank all those who submi ed essays for this issue; reading, edi ng, and publishing your work has been an absolute pleasure. The hard work of the Essay Editors and Design Team at the History Journal is greatly appreciated and the con nuing success we have enjoyed pays tribute to this. We wish to congratulate all those who were successful in their submissions. We also wish to thank the History Department for their unwavering support, without which the History Journal would not be able to hold its monthly academic events or publish its biannual issues. We hope you enjoy reading this year’s Winter Print. Graciously yours, Shabbir Bokhari (Editor in Chief) & Catriona Tassell (Commissioning Editor) 1 Like the History Journal on /QueenMaryHistoryJournal Follow the History Journal on @QMHUJ 2 Winter Issue László Zorya The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine Contents Compare and contrast the idea of ‘nation’ developed in two Compare and contrast the idea of ‘na on’ developed in 4 countries in the period before 1848. Romania and the Ukraine in the period before 1848. László Zorya László Zorya What did the wearing of the veil signify to medieval 15 In a 1973 essay, poli cal philosopher John Plamenatz iden fied a dis nc on Muslim men and women? between what he described as "Western" and "Eastern" na onalisms, characterised Bethany Price by imita on and illiberalism.1 Plamenatz argues - whilst neglec ng to actually define How extensively did the prin ng of maps modify intellectual, 31 Economic, and social life in Europe between 1450 and 1650? extensively from Western na onalisms, and that this necessitated na onal leaders Harry Sophocleous ‘Iden ty is a knife’: Must tribal iden Eastern Europe - that the na onalisms that emerged there were borrowed forcibly imposing these na onalisms on popula ons. Scep cal of the u lity of such a generalisa on, this essay will consider the specific nature of Romanian and Ukrainian es be repressed in order for African States to avoid internal violent conflict? 48 Sebas an Lowe na onalisms, as a case study. Plamenatz believed "Eastern" na onalisms assumed their defining characteris cs at their concep on, and thus the essay will focus on the emergence and development of na onalism in the Romanian and Ukrainian lands in Analyse the main differences between the u litarianism of Jeremy 63 the early nineteenth century. Bentham and that of John Stuart Mill There are obvious seman c issues in using the terms “Romanian” and Sam Allen “Ukrainian” to refer to members of those na ons before the na ons can be said to Assess the significance of the Iran-Contra Affair. Harry Sophocleous 77 have defini vely existed. Therefore, for the purposes of this essay, “Romanian” refers to the people of Transylvania and the Danubian Provinces of Wallachia and Moldavia, 3 4 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal László Zorya who were or who would later be considered ethnically Romanian. “Ukrainian” shall In turn, these Greek na onalists influenced Romanians who were encouraged to refer to the people of the Russian Empire, who were or who would later be fight on behalf of the Greeks.3 Romanians in the Danubian Provinces perceived considered ethnically Ukrainian. themselves to have suffered equal or greater oppression under the rule of the The term “Ruthenian” will be used when men oning their counterparts in the Habsburg Empire. The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine ignominious Phanariot Greeks than the Greeks themselves did under the O oman The most immediate aspect which ought to be recognised of Romanian and Turks.4 Thus, when Greek na onal leader Alexander Ypsilan s appealed to Romanian Ukrainian na onalism is that neither can be seen to have been borne out of a na onal leader Tudor Vladimirescu for help in the fight against Turks, Vladimirescu struggle, as was French na onalism in the Revolu on; German na onalism in the reportedly offered to help Ypsilan s, “go home, so he could have his revolu on libera on from Napoleon; or Serb and Greek na onalisms in wars against the there”.5 O omans. Rather, the development of both Romanian and Ukrainian na onalism Of vital importance to the na onalist movement in the Ukrainian lands were was the result of a protracted campaign conducted by an educated elite. the intelligentsia, the rela ve few who possessed an educa on, and whose In Romania, the first step in this development came during the French ideological convic ons mo vated them to culturally, socially and poli cally “improve” Enlightenment from Transylvanian Uniate theological students that were educated the peasantry. Most of the intelligentsia who hailed from this region were of Cossack in Vienna and Rome. Vienna was an enlightened city with the ideals of the French descent, and whose noble status (starshyna) had been between 1785 and 1835 philosophes circula ng widely amongst merchants and diplomats who maintained recognized by the Russian Empire, then rescinded, and eventually granted once direct connec ons with French counterparts. These ideals reached and inspired the more, though selec vely so. Transylvanian Uniate students who would later lead the na onalist movement.2 In order to jus fy, and therefore protect, this nobility, many intellectuals of Cossack The Enlightenment ideals also reached the cultural radius of Constan nople, descent began examining past trea es and chronicles to prove the equivalence of where it profoundly influenced Greek na onalists to plan the Greek War of the Cossack starshyna and the Russian nobility (dvoryanstvo).6 In doing so, these Independence (1821). Cossacks inadvertently became the first Ukrainian historians. Their histories exhibit a deep patrio sm and nostalgia for the old Cossack Hetmanate. Istoriia Rusov (1800), 5 6 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal László Zorya for example, asserted that the people living under the Hetmanate enjoyed the same The Cossack Hetmanate and Dacia were considered by the Ukrainian and Romanian rights and liber es associated with the Enlightenment. However, these early na onalists to be their na on’s Golden Age. The Golden Age is a vital aspect of Ukrainian histories generally accepted Ukraine to be an integral component of na onalism, both in impar ng a sense of legi macy to the na on and in imbuing it Imperial Russia and did not a empt to jus fy or promote succession. with pres ge. The Golden Age also offers a contrast with the na on's degraded The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine History also became a key component of Romanian na onalism, for as well as present and a jus fica on for its eleva on to a utopian des ny. In neither the absorbing the ideals of the French Enlightenment in Vienna, the Transylvanian Uniate Ukrainian nor the Romanian case, however, can this des ny be seen to have students were inspired by the architectural grandeur of Rome, par cularly its Ancient superiority over other na ons, but rather, equality. Where Ukrainian na onalists Roman monuments.7 They were also struck by the similarity of their na ve Romanian were mo vated to a ain an equal standing with the Russian nobility, Transylvanian language to that of the Italians and came to view themselves as related to the na onalists sought either a revoca on or altera on of the medieval pact of “Unio Italians, and therefore of Roman descent, as Italians were considered to be. It was trium na onum”, which granted na onhood and therefore rela ve poli cal beneficial that the boundaries of the Roman province of Dacia were considered to autonomy to Magyars, Saxons and Szekleys, but not to Romanians, thus excluding have been roughly correspondent to the poli cal boundaries of early nineteenth- the la er from poli cal life.10 Keen to emphasise the La nity of their na on and thus century Transylvania.8 Thus it was at this me that the term “Romanian” became afford it a cultural eminence, Gheorghe Șincai and Samuil Micu collaborated on a adopted to refer to the people and their language previously referred to as Wallach, grammar, The Elements of the Daco-Roman or Wallachian Language (1780), to emphasising their La n origins. Histories were wri en by Uniate priests, such as codify the Romanian language and accentuate its La n origins. This grammar thus Petru Maior in History of the Origin of the Roumanians in Dacia (1812), that marks the start of a concerted campaign by Romanian intellectuals to replace the portrayed Dacia as a cultural and poli cal idyll and a empted to illustrate a clear line tradi onal Cyrillic alphabet in which their language appeared in religious texts with of descent between the Dacians and contemporary Romanians.9 This gave Romanian the Roman alphabet and a purging of words of non-La n origin from the language.11 na onalism a mission, as Romanians were seen to be defenders of an eastern La n The Ukrainian language experienced no similar reform in the Russian Empire. It was culture; as well as a dignity: a superiority over the Magyars, Germans, and Szekleys. not even being considered a language but rather a dialect of Russian, known as “Li le Russian”.12 In the Habsburg lands, Ruthenian na onalism was 7 8 handicapped Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal László Zorya The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine by the near total illiteracy of the peasant popula on and the almost complete that, through its La n links, Romanian was related to Italian and, most Polonisa on of its social and intellectual elite.13 However, keen to reduce the importantly, French. Many of these na onalists, such as Ion Heliade Rădulescu and influence both of the Polish elite and of the neighbouring Russian Empire, the Anton Pann, began to publish original literary works and translated classics into their Habsburgs encouraged the development of the Ruthenian language, dis nct from language to evidence its cultural worth. Polish and Russian, inadvertently crea ng a language remarkably similar to The Ukrainian intelligentsia also became interested in developing a literature in their Ukrainian.14 It is because of this that Ruthenians began to iden fy with Ukrainian language, inspired primarily by the German Roman c, Johann Go ried Herder. It na onalism and, despite exis ng in incredibly different poli cal situa ons, the two was Herder who first challenged the view that some na ons were devoid of culture, groups empathised with one another so that in 1848 the only Ukrainian uprising was arguing instead that culture was universal. Herder was also convinced of the primacy a response to the aboli on of Ruthenian serfdom. of language, wondering, “Has a people anything dearer than the speech of its Historian Stephen Fisher-Gala argues that there was no real liaison between fathers? In its speech resides its whole thought domain, its tradi on, history, Wallachian and Moldavian na onalists, as existed between Ruthenians and religion, and basis of life, all its heart and soul”.16 This inspired Ukrainians to collate Ukrainians, let alone between them and Transylvanian na onalists; however, it is cultural collec ons. Par cularly notable was the collec on of Ukrainian folk songs clear that these different na onalist groups empathised with one another.15 For compiled by Prince Nikolai Tsertelev and Mykhailo Maksymovych, who argued that example, Transylvanian Uniate priests were vehemently opposed to a empts to alter the content and moral quality of the folk songs differen ated them from those of their Church doctrine in order to assimilate it with the Roman Catholic Church. Given other na ons, par cularly Russians.17 However, by 1848 Ukrainian literature was the Transylvanian na onalists' apparent proclivity towards any other La nising trend, nowhere near as developed, nor as respected, as Romanian literature, hindered by this seems bizarre un l one considers that such a change would have resulted in crass works such as Ivan Kotlyarevsky’s travesty of Virgil’s Aeneid, Eneyida (1798) greater differen a on between the Transylvanians and the Orthodox Danubian which, wri en in a jocular, folksy style, appeared to lend credence to claims that Romanians. Prior to the nineteenth century, the Romanian and Ukrainian languages Ukrainian was a language unsuitable for discussing lo ier themes.18 were considered primi ve and therefore capable only of expressing the most basic, In the 1830s and 1840s the Romanian na onalists became increasingly domes c thoughts. This view was challenged by Romanian na onalists’ asser ons poli cal, in contrast to the previous genera on, whose aims had been primarily 9 10 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal László Zorya cultural.19 The development of culture apparently indicated a cultural superiority considered primarily cultural movements involving the inven on of languages, over Magyars, Turks, and Slavs and at least equality with Germans and Greeks. research of histories and development of literary movements. Although elements of Subjuga on under these peoples could no longer be jus fied. In Wallachia and both na onalisms were borrowed from foreign sources, par cularly in the case of Moldavia, the revolu onaries of 1848 were primarily concerned with social Romanian na onalism, there was no a empt to imitate any foreign na on per se. revolu on and poli cal independence, and showed li le concern for a unifica on of Instead, Romanian na onalism borrowed aspects of Italian and French na onalism the Danubian Provinces with Transylvania. Nor did Transylvanians seek unifica on, or to emphasise aspects of the na on which were pre-exis ng and perceived to be even independence, but rather a strengthening of the rights of the Romanian middle La n whilst Ukrainian na onalists adopted the thoughts of Herder, not to copy class and intelligentsia, as well as the emancipa on of the peasantry.20 Romanian German na onalism but to jus fy their cultural output. Since neither Romanian nor na onalism in 1848, then, manifested itself in demands for equality and Ukrainian na onalists had states to support them, they could hardly impose their self-determina on, but not for hegemony. na onalism on a popula on unless it was willing and neither group agitated for The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine In the Russian Empire, Ukrainian na onalists did not commit to any significant hegemony, only demanding equal standing with other na ons as a natural right of uprising comparable to those in Transylvania and the Danubian provinces. However, their na on. Plamenatz’s generalisa on regarding the nature of na onalism in demands were made to introduce teaching in the Ukrainian language in areas where Eastern Europe is invalid, a predictable conclusion given his failure to even a empt Ukrainians were in the majority. Ruthenians, meanwhile, pe to define the region. oned for their clergy to receive rights equal to that of other na ons of the Habsburg Empire and for the 21 establishment of a Ruthenian Council. Notes The emancipa on of the Ruthenian 1. John Plamenatz, 'Two Types of Na onalism' in Eugene Kamenka (ed.), Na onalism: Evolu on of an Idea (Canberra: Australian Na onal University Press, 1973) pp. 34- 38. 2. John Campbell, French Influence and the Rise of Roumanian Na onalism (New York: Arno Press, 1971) pp. 7- 8. 3. Stephen Fischer-Gala , Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas, Neue Folge, Bd. 12, H. 1 (May 1964). p. 49. 4. R.W. Seton-Watson, A History of the Roumanians: From Roman Times to the Comple on of Unity (London: Archon Books, 1964). p. 196. 5. Keith Hitchens,The Romanians 1774- 1866 (Oxford: Claredon Press, 1996). p. 202. 6. Paul Robert Magocsi, A History of Ukraine, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996). p. 356. peasantry also provoked a small Ukrainian uprising in the Russian lands in support of a similar libera on being granted there. Again, none of these demands can be considered ones which would elevate the Ukrainians or Ruthenians to a standing above other na ons.22 In summary, prior to 1848, Romanian and Ukrainian should be considered 11 12 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal László Zorya The idea of ‘na on’ in Romania and the Ukraine Bibliography Notes 1. Campbell, French Influence and the Rise of Roumanian Na onalism. pp. 23- 24. Secondary literature 2. Seton-Watson, A History of the Roumanians p. 272 Hayes, Carlton J.H., Essays on Na onalism, (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1928). 3. Ibid. pp 272- 273. 4. Fischer-Gala , Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas. p. 48. Hitchens, Keith; The Rumanian Na onal Movement in Transylvania 1780- 1849 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969). 5. Campbell, French Influence and the Rise of Roumanian Na onalism. p. 26. Hitchens, Keith; The Romanians 1774- 1866 (Oxford: Claredon Press, 1996). 6. Magocsi, A History of Ukraine, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996) p. 358. Kann, Robert A.; A History of the Habsburg Empire, 1526- 1918, (Berkley: University of California Press, 1974). 7. Robert A. Kann, The Mul na onal Empire: Na onalism and Na onal Reform in the Habsburg Monarchy 1848-1918, (New York: Octagon Books, 1964) p. 326. 8. Robert A. Kann, A History of the Habsburg Empire, 1526- 1918, (Berkley: University of California Press, 1974) pp. 392- 394. 9. Stephen Fischer-Gala , Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas p. 50. 10. G. von Herder, Briefe zur Beförderung der Humanität, cited in Carlton J.H.Hayes, Essays on Na onalism (New York: The Macmillan Company, 1928) p. 13. 11. Magocsi, A History of Ukraine, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996) p. 356. 12. Ibid. p. 358. 13. Keith Hitchins, The Rumanian Na onal Movement in Transylvania 1780- 1849 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1969). p. 135. 14. Stephen Fischer-Gala , Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas p. 52.. 15. Orest Subtelny, Ukraine: A History (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2009) p. 326. 16. Ibid. p. 335. Subtelny, Orest; Ukraine: A History (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2009) . Kann, Robert A.; The Mul na onal Empire: Na onalism and Na onal Reform in the Habsburg Monarchy 1848-1918, (New York: Octagon Books, 1964) . Magocsi, Paul Robert; A History of Ukraine, (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996). Plamenatz, John; 'Two Types of Na onalism' in Eugene Kamenka (ed.), Na onalism: Evolu on of an Idea (Canberra: Australian Na onal University Press, 1973) . Seton-Watson, R.W.; A History of the Roumanians: From Roman Times to the Comple on of Unity (London: Archon Books, 1964). Bibliography Secondary literature Campbell, John; French Influence and the Rise of Roumanian Na onalism (New York: Arno Press, 1971). Fischer-Gala , Stephen; Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas, Neue Folge, Bd. 12, H. 1 (May 1964). 13 14 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal What did the wearing of the veil signify to medieval Muslim men and omen? Bethany Price The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women There is even evidence that Muhammad explained that the man has to please and sa sfy the woman, not just to think about himself.3 In turn, the context of the revela on has to be ques oned. It would seem that there are a number of reasons Bethany Price At first glance it would be easy to state that the veil signified the separa on of spheres for medieval Muslim men and women, which to a far extent is true. However, there is a significant and important gap between men’s ideal of the veil and women’s prac ce of the veil. Therefore, it would be more accurate to argue that the wearing of the veil held, and s ll holds for people today, a plethora of meanings for medieval men and women. Indeed, Mernissi accurately summarised that the concept of the veil is three-dimensional and that these dimensions o en interplay with each other. The first dimension is visual; the root of the verb hajaba means to hide. The second is spa al: to separate or mark a border. The final is ethical and so which imply the veil was implemented because of unique contextual factors. For example, Mernissi highlighted that Year 5 of the Heijra – the year the veil was introduced - was a par cularly catastrophic year for military defeats and that Muhammad was red of his enemies following his wives in the street.4 In addi on, it has quite recently been argued that this pivotal veil verse did not fit in with Muhammad’s normal pa ern for a revela on; there was no wai ng or thinking period.5 Furthermore, perhaps the most important and influen al factor at the me was the pressure from Umar Ibn al-Kha ab, a close associate of Muhammad, who was a prominent spokesman in favour of women’s seclusion.6 The context of the veil revela on is therefore crucial, it can convincingly be argued that the Prophet did not 1 the veil demarks the realm of the forbidden. And yet, even this perhaps rigid structure does not reliably inform us of the o en fluid and personal significance of the veil. want to implement the veil or the ins tu on which came to be inseparable from it. Umar Ibn al-Kha ab and his views were shared by many other men in medieval Islamic socie es. The idea of women not being veiled and them par cipa ng in the Muhammad’s revela ons in the Qur’an that seemingly mandated his wives, if public sphere was abhorrent to some but not to Muhammad. There is much not all Muslim women, should be veiled are clearly central to this ques on. evidence of his wives influencing him and taking an ac ve part in poli cs.7 This was Although, it has to be men oned that there is evidence that Muhammad did not perhaps too innova ve for most medieval men. This was because in pre-Islamic intend to establish an ins tu on of isola on for women, rather the opposite. society, it has been argued, women experienced daily violence and harassment Mernissi recently reassessed and argued that the dawn of Islam was supposed to go under the humilia ng prac ce of ta’arrud and o en remained at home.8 hand in hand with egalitarianism and that all should be equal in this new faith.2 15 16 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price It was against this backdrop that the veil was supported, o en under the premise is the idea that women are passive and that men are dominant.12 that it would protect free women. In the newly formed Islamic socie es there were a empts to excuse this harassment with men arguing that they thought unveiled women were slaves and that this explained why Allah had revealed the wives should pull their jilbab over themselves, to make themselves known and to protect themselves.9 Moreover, this is supported somewhat in Mamluk socie es where concubines had to be veiled, in contrast to ordinary slave girls who did not. Ibn Taymiyah explained this was not because the veil was a personal status symbol for the concubines. It was rather for their protec on and probably because their owners wanted to ensure no other man touched them, so the veil also protected them but for unscrupulous reasons. 10 It would seem then that the hijab was necessary to mark which women ta’arrud could be commi ed against and to protect the others.11 However, in truth it would seem that men supported the veil because it suited their desired patriarchal society. It perhaps must be men oned though that Muslim writers have largely influenced these ideas of the apparent brutal reality of pre-Islamic socie es, and of course it is in their interest to present Islam as a posi ve improvement for women, or to at least be providing protec on for women. This only further supports the idea that Muslim men supported the veil mainly because it limited women to the domes c sphere. Moreover, to truly understand this medieval male Islamic a tude towards women, it is necessary to consider the two theories of women’s sexuality. The prevailing contemporary belief is the explicit theory, which 17 The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women However, driven far into Muslim unconsciousness, and championed by Imam Ghazali, is the implicit theory which was dominant in the Middle Ages.13 This belief contains the idea that society struggles to cope with women and their destruc ve power. Fears of women’s deadly sexuality existed, and perhaps s ll exist, and in turn the idea that they had the power to seduce all men. Moreover, according to Ghazli the biggest gi from Allah is the ability to reason. In order to prevent men from being distracted and to appreciate this gi it was argued that women must be veiled.14 An understanding of this concept goes some way to explain the framework of medieval Muslim men’s thoughts. To gain the most precise idea of the origins of the veil in Islam it is necessary to scru nise Muhammad’s revela on regarding the hijab. It was wri en that whenever someone asked for something from Muhammad’s wives (‘his ladies’) they should have asked ‘from before a screen: that makes for greater purity in your hearts and for theirs’.15 In understanding this it seems obvious that the verse might only apply to Muhammad’s wives, however, Qur’anic instruc ons addressed to the wives were apparently also naturally seen as valid for Muslim women and so the ins tu on of the veil was established.16 Indeed Stowasser has argued that the veil was expanded both seman cally and legally because the hijab was also linked to the mantle verse (33.59) and the modesty verse (24.31). In turn, the veil was stretched to be a concept and not merely literally something women wore. 18 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women Overall, the effects of the veil revela on were monumental in so far as it became an Furthermore, it would seem that similar to Islamic socie es, in Jewish ideology. The pairing of key Qur’anic terms such as ‘hijab’ and ‘confinement’ communi es in medieval Cairo, clothes were supposed to ensure that females were intertwined the two to the extent that they were inseparable. The veil meant, and invisible. At a glance there are some differences between Jewish and Muslim o en s ll means, more than concealing; it means seclusion ‘a domes c fixture to communi es, for example, mantles and outerwear were important for both sexes in ensure seclusion and also the seclusion itself.’17 The original view of an egalitarian regard to respect and piety, especially when entering a House of Worship. To be Islam began to disappear. Instead, the absolute division of private and public spheres completely covered was to be dignified. However, despite basic items of clothing was established, or more precisely women’s isola on from the public sphere.18 It is being iden cal in form, their purpose differed. Crucially, similar to Islamic socie es, therefore clear that at the me of the revela on the veil meant the complete the aim of clothes for women in the public sphere was for the women to be separa on of spheres because it perfectly suited, and was perhaps needed, to ‘inconspicuous, if not invisible’. This is in contrast to men whose clothing should uphold the patriarchal society.19 show him to be male.23 The veil, again, is inexplicably intertwined with invisibility and seclusion. In addi on to the Qur’anic verses there are many Hadiths that support the wearing of the veil. It is recorded by Abu Dawud (2:641) that Muhammad clarified that a young woman should not leave the house unveiled.20 And it is recorded by Bukhari (6: 321) that Allah does not accept the prayers of a woman who is unveiled.21 However, similar to there being flaws in the context in which the revela on was revealed, Mernissi has argued that the Hadiths were open to corrup on. It has been proven that authors sold themselves to poli cians who desired to influence the Hadith so it would benefit them. There is even evidence of authors being paid to invent informa on regarding poems wri en and recited by Muhammad.22 In turn, this only reinforces that in the Middle Ages Muslim men wanted women to be secluded and went to great lengths to ensure this happened. 19 It has clearly been established that Muslim men desired to veil women – in the ins tu onal sense of the word – but what remains to be ques oned is the reality of Muslim women wearing the veil and women who followed other religions. Zilfi argued broadly that slavery and the oppression of women was s ll present in the O oman Empire. Women were s ll bound to the house late in the nineteenth century with the separate spheres of men and women being very much the norm.24 In the eighteenth century Osman III mandated that all women should cover their bodies, seemingly because he found them disgus ng, and yet his decrees also carried religious weight because the only excep ons to dress codes were granted by Holy Law.25 Despite Osman’s specific misogyny perhaps being unique his two 20 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price successors reinforced that veils which revealed women’s faces were not to be conversing and humouring the shop owners’.30 Moreover, he chas sed women for tolerated. Indeed, Zilfi concluded that ‘misogyny and zealous enforcement of female showing their wrists, implying they are veiled but not fully covered.31 This is clear propriety were two sides of the same coin’ in the late O oman Empire.26 And yet, by evidence that in Egyp an Mamluk society in the fourteenth century the reality was mid-eighteenth century women were taking more risks. Billowing sleeves and tall that women who wore veils did not adhere to the ideology of the veil and all that it headdresses began to appear, they were immediately forbidden but, importantly, entailed; the veil did not translate as an ins tu on of isola on for them, and if it did were being tried.27 Overall, the fact that Osman and three of his successors felt the they apparently ignored it. need to reinforce the wearing of veils implies that women did not share the same a tude towards veils as the men wri ng the laws. There is clearly an indica on that men were manda ng that the veil should be worn and to them it was linked to female modesty and seclusion. The women also seemingly understood the meaning of the veil and hence began to a empt to change their clothing. The idea that women did not agree with men’s ideal of the veil is most clearly evident in Lu i’s examina on of Ibn al-Hajj’s trea se on fourteenth-century Cairene women.28 On the face of it, Ibn al-Hajj’s work seems to strengthen the idea that Muslim men wished to control women, and that they viewed the public sphere of men and the private sphere of women to be separate. Indeed, this exclusion of women was informed by the implicit sexual theory: females threatened the order of the male world. Any mixing of these spheres was seen to be promo ng chaos.29 However, by implica on, his work also suggests Cairene women did not desire and did not abide by the ins tu on of seclusion. Ibn al-Hajj complained that women The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women It seems there are clear dispari es between men’s ideal of the veil and women’s reality of it. Kahf has argued the veil obviously predates Islam and that throughout history, in prac ce, only the privileged could have worn a veil. It was a status symbol for those who wore one.32 In the Epic of Gilgamesh (ca. 2000 B.C.E) the young woman who guarded the gate is veiled and Kahf linked this to her having had some primal power because she can see without being seen and know with being known.33 The Prophet Muhammad is even noted in Persian miniatures as being veiled so as to preserve his image from becoming too common.34 In understanding these examples there is also much evidence of medieval Muslim women using the veil as a tool of empowerment. Similar to its use in Gilgamesh, the veil is portrayed to have been used by medieval Muslim women to cover themselves to their advantage. When wearing a veil a woman can see all and see everyone else but people cannot see her. Indeed, they could ‘openly scru nise men’.35 were were talking in the street and mee ng in shops to gossip for ‘several hours, 21 22 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price Furthermore, from the account of a German knight on a pilgrimage in the late fi eenth-century we can learn that the veil is apparently used by Muslim women to conceal themselves from their husbands so that they can visit a soldier or knight to The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women it represented this, or acknowledged the veil and used it to their advantage, which is echoed in today’s society. So far it has become apparent that not only is there a gap between the ideal 36 ‘take their pleasure with him for three or four hours.’ The veil was also subject to fashion, regardless of class. In Egypt the qina was a metre long and not very wide. This is in contrast to Bagdad where the mi’jar was a black veil, made of muslin and and the reality of veiling, but alongside this, that the veil varies widely in its significance. Ahmed has wri en broadly on the meaning of the veil in today’s society. She seems to argue, like others, that the veil’s meaning is not sta c or fixed 37 was perfumed with hyacinth. Bedouin women even decorated their headdresses with jewellery or silver and gold coins.38 By Muslim women personalising their veil they were perhaps subconsciously figh ng against the anonymity furthered by the ins tu on of wearing a veil. Overall, from this it might be concluded that aside from its proposed use by men in Islam, veiling was used in a posi ve way, for men and women. It was perhaps only with the dawn of Islam that the wearing the veil became an ideology and in turn some Muslim women chose to use the veil to their advantage. and that it s ll changes today.40 In the places where it is mandatory it is s ll oppressive, but where it is op onal for women it can mean many different things, for example, Ahmed argued it can be a call for minori es to be treated equally; a call for social jus ce.41 Stowasser supported the idea of a seman c shi in that the hijab is becoming more literally a way of dress than a way of life.42 She argued that the reason for this is, in part, because when families have a low-income, women go out in the public sphere and work.43 Furthermore, Afshar maintained that supporters of Islam have argued that the veil can be libera ng by allowing women to be humans Further to this, Muslim women rejec ng the veil and all it represented is perhaps epitomised by Sukayna, one of the great-granddaughters of the Prophet. She revolted against the ‘oppressive, despo c Islam’ and dismissed everything that rather than mere sex objects.44 However, it is undeniable that in some, if not most, areas the veil is not free from poli cal links. Charrad’s case study of Tunisia is revealing. He iden fied that Islamists 39 limited her including the veil. She married five men whilst pledging exclusivity to none but demanding it from each of them and she took an ac ve part in poli cs and poetry. This is obviously an extreme example but goes some way to prove that some enforce the veil in Algeria with the aim for the women to not look cheap and materialis c, values probably associated with the West. However, in Tunisia the veil is not enforced – some women wear it by choice.45 Muslim women rejected being secluded and either rejected the veil because 23 24 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women There are two types of veil in Tunisia. The tradi onal safsari, which changes This is tenta vely shown in the O oman Empire but more explicitly portrayed according to regions, is very old and filled with tradi on. The other is the hijab which through Ibn al-Hajj’s trea se on Cairene women. In Egypt it seems that the veil arrived in Tunisia in the 1970s and 1980s. It has no regional uniqueness and is very signified an ideology of isola on but was apparently somewhat ignored. The much related to Islamism – note that here Islamism means fundamental Islam.46 It is difference between the ideal and the reality of the veil is prominently shown a similar situa on in Egypt where Stowasser argued that fundamentalists wear the through the varying examples of its meaning to women; it was a fashion symbol, to hijab whereas educated women tend to wear the hijab qua.47 The veil is clearly s ll be used for their empowerment and to their advantage. Finally, in today’s society associated with iden ty and poli cs but the important idea is that some women are the ins tu on of the veil has progressed further and is perhaps more obviously choosing to wear a veil and in turn are deciding what the veil means to them. being rejected. Instead, women are using it in their own personal way. Indeed, it may actually signify today, in some instances, what Muhammad apparently ini ally It seems true then that the veil did not and does not have a sta c or fixed intended for Islam to give to women. significance. At the me of the revela on it seems to have been introduced under Notes the premise that it provided protec on for women. However, in truth, it seems that 1. F., Mernissi, Women and Islam. An Historical and Theological Enquiry (Oxford, 1991), p. 93. 2. Ibid, p. 163. 3. F., Mernissi, Beyond the Veil. Male-Female Dynamics in Muslim Society (Massachuse s, 2011), p. 51. 4. Mernissi, Women and Islam, p. 86. 5. Ibid, p. 106. 6. Ibid. 7. Ibid, p. 163. 8. Ibid, p. 180. 9. Ibid. 10. R., Yossef, ‘Women and Gender in Mamluk Society – an Overview’, Mamluk Studies Review 11/2 (2007), (pp. 1-47) p. 12. 11. Mernissi, Women and Islam, p. 187. 12. Mernissi, Beyond the Veil, p. 42. the ins tu on of the veil was needed by the patriarchal society and was needed to combat the fear of women’s sexuality, but also because any other posi on of women was too innova ve for the Middle Ages. Despite Muhammad’s apparent inten ons, the veil signified the separa on of the public and private spheres. And although as Islam spread, and was moulded as it came into contact with other diverse cultures, it seems that the veil also represented invisibility in Jewish socie es in the Arab world and in the O oman Empire. However, throughout different cultures and me periods there is a significant gap between man’s ideal and woman’s reality of the veil. 25 26 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price Notes 13. Imam., Ghazali, Revivifica on of Religious Sciences, vol. II, Chapter on Marriage 14. h p://www.ghazali.org/works/marriage.htm 15. [Accessed on 21/11/14]. 16. The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women Notes 35. M., Zilfi, Women and Slavery in the Late O oman Empire: The Design of Difference (Cambridge, 2010), p. 84. 36. H., Lu i, ‘Manners and customs of Fourteenth-Century Cairene Women: Female Anarchy versus Male Shar‘i Order in Muslim Prescrip ve Trea se’, in N. Keddie and B. Baron (eds.), Women in Middle Eastern History (New Haven, 1992). Mernissi, Beyond the Veil, p. 42. 37. Ibid, p. 100. 17. Qur’an Chapter 33, Verse 53 38. Ibid, p. 103. 18. h p://quran.com/33 39. Ibid, p. 104. 40. 19. [Accessed on 21/11/14]. M., Kahf, ‘From Her Royal Body the Robe was Removed: the Blessings of the Veil and the Trauma of Forced Unveilings in the Middle East’, in J. Heath (eds.) The Veil: Women Writers on Its History, Lore, and Poli cs (London, 2008), p. 30. 20. F., Stowasser, Women in the Qur’an, Tradi ons, and Interpreta on (Oxford, 1994), p. 92. 41. Ibid, p. 30. 42. Ibid. 43. S., Guthrie, Arab Women in the Middle Ages. Private Lives and Public Roles (London, 2001), p. 124. 44. A German knight on the women of Cairo, from The Pilgrimage of Arnold von Harff (1496-1499 AD) (London, 1946), p. 123-4. 45. Ibid, p. 122. 21. Ibid, p. 91. 22. Mernissi, Women and Islam, p. 187. 23. Ibid, p. 185. 24. A., Dawud, (2:641) 25. h p://www.usc.edu/org/cmje/religious-texts/hadith/abudawud/032sat.php#032.4092 46. Ibid, p. 124. 26. [Accessed on 21/11/14]. 47. Mernissi, Women and Islam, p. 192. 27. Bukhari (6:321) 48. L., Ahmed, A Quiet Revolu on; the Veil’s Resurgence, from the Middle East to America (London, 2011), p. 212. 28. h p://www.usc.edu/org/cmje/religious-texts/hadith/bukhari/006sbt.php#001.006.321 49. Ibid, p. 211. 29. [Accessed on 21/11/14]. 50. Stowasser, Women in the Qur’an, p. 129. 30. Mernissi, Women and Islam, p. 45. 51. Ibid, p. 129. 31. S., D., Goitein, A Mediterranean Society: the Jewish Communi es of the Arab World as Portrayed in the Documents of the Cairo Geniza, vol. 4 (Berkeley, 1999), p. 155. 52. H., ‘Afshar, Western Inven on on Arab Womanhood: the Oriental Woman’, in H. Afshar (eds.) Women in the Middle East. Percep ons, Reali es and Struggles for Liberaon (Basingstoke, 1993), p. 12. 32. M., Zilfi, Women and Slavery in the Late O oman Empire: The Design of Difference (Cambridge, 2010), p. 73. 53. 33. Ibid, p. 73. M. M., Charrad, ‘Cultural Diversity within Islam: Veils and Laws in Tunisia’, in H. Bodman and N. Tohidi (eds.), Women in Muslim Socie es. Diversity within Unity (London, 1998), p. 65. 34. Ibid, p. 74. 54. Ibid, p. 65. 27 28 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bethany Price Notes 55. The significance of the veil for Muslim men and women Bibliography Primary literature Stowasser, Women in the Qur’an, p. 130. Bibliography Bukhari (6:321) h p://www.usc.edu/org/cmje/religious-texts/hadith/bukhari/006-sbt.php#001.006.321 Secondary literature [Accessed on 21/11/14] Afshar, H., ‘Western Inven on on Arab Womanhood: the Oriental Woman’, in H. Afshar (eds.) Women in the Middle East. Percep ons, Reali es and Struggles for Libera on (Basingstoke, 1993). Ahmed, L., A Quiet Revolu on; the Veil’s Resurgence, from the Middle East to America (London, 2011). Dawud, Abu, (2:641) h p://www.usc.edu/org/cmje/religious-texts/hadith/abudawud/032-sat.php#032.4092 [Accessed on 21/11/14] Charrad, M. M., ‘Cultural Diveristy within Islam: Veils and Laws in Tunisia’, in H. Bodman and N. Tohidi (eds.), Women in Muslim Socie es. Diversity within Unity (London, 1998). German knight on the women of Cairo, from The Pilgrimage of Arnold von Harff (1496-1499 AD), (London, 1946) Goitein, S. D, A Mediterranean Society: the Jewish Communi es of the Arab World as Portrayed in the Documents of the Cairo Geniza, vol. 4 (Berkeley, 1999). Ghazali, Imam, Revivifica on of Religious Sciences, vol. II, Chapter on Marriage Guthrie, S., Arab Women in the Middle Ages. Private Lives and Public Roles (London, 2001). Heath, J (ed.), The veil: women writers on its history, lore, and poli cs (London, 2008). Kahf, M. ‘From Her Royal Body the Robe was Removed: the Blessings of the Veil and the Trauma of Forced Unveilings in the Middle East’, in J. Heath (eds.) The Veil: Women Writers on Its History, Lore, and Poli cs (London, 2008). Lu i, H., ‘Manners and customs of Fourteenth-Century Cairene Women: Female Anarchy versus Male Shar‘i Order in Muslim Prescrip ve Trea se’, in N. Keddie and B. Baron (eds.), Women in Middle Eastern History (New Haven, 1992). h p://www.ghazali.org/works/marriage.htm [Accessed on 21/11/14] Qur’an Chapter 33, Verse 53 h p://quran.com/33 [Accessed on 21/11/14] Mernissi, F., Beyond the Veil. Male-Female Dynamics in Muslim Society (Massachuse s, 2011). Mernissi, F., Women and Islam. An Historical and Theological Enquiry (Oxford, 1991). Stowasser, F., Women in the Qur’an, Tradi ons, and Interpreta on (Oxford, 1994). Yossef, R., ‘Women and Gender in Mamluk Society – an Overview’, Mamluk Studies Review 11/2 (2007), pp. 1-47. Zilfi, M., Women and Slavery in the Difference, (Cambridge, 2010). 29 Late O oman Empire: The Design of 30 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 woodcut print that showcased the New World, branding the con nent for the first How extensively did the printing of maps modify me in history as ‘America’ (Figure 1). The cartographer offered an explana on: ‘Since another, fourth part [of the world] has been discovered by Americus intellectual, economic and social life in Europe between 1450 and 1650? Harry Sophocleous Vespu us…I do not see why anyone should object to it being called a er Americus the discover, a man of natural wisdom, Land of Americus or America’.4 And America it became; such is the power of maps. Waldseemüller was just one among many who was able to benefit from the prin ng press in driving the cartographical field ‘We should note the force, effect, and consequences of inven ons which are nowhere more conspicuous than in those three which were unknown to the ancients, namely, prin ng, gunpowder, and the compass. For these three have changed forward to an extent that is recognizable to all in the modern-age. However, in recent years, the impact of the prin ng press has increasingly the appearance and state of the whole world’. become the subject of vitriolic debate. In par cular, Elizabeth Eisenstein’s asser on Francis Bacon, Novum Organum (1620).1 that the technology was an ‘agent of change’ has been ques oned by Adrian Johns’ ‘Journey all over the universe in a map, without the expense The Nature of the Book.5 It is the tle of the la er’s study that exposes gaping holes and fa gue of travelling, without suffering the inconveniences of heat, cold, hunger, and thirst’. Migues de Cervantes, Don Quixote (1605-1615).2 in the historiographical field. Much has been said about the impact of the inven on of prin ng on literacy and ways of library, but less has been wri en about the Mar n Waldseemüller (c.1470-c.1521), a renowned German scholar, equally momentous impact of print upon the circula on and communica on of humanist, cleric, and most of all, cartographer, moved to Basle in the early 1500’s visual informa on. By overlooking the importance of cartography, our where he came into contact with the well-known printer Johannes Amerbach. It is understanding of this important technological innova on on European life is through Amerbach that Waldseemüller was able to learn how to translate his subsequently limited. As a result, this essay will argue that the impact of the humanist educa on in cosmography and mapmaking into the kind of printed maps movable type prin ng press on the cartographical industry possessed shockwaves that were surfacing during the early sixteenth century.3 In 1507, within the confines that altered European life forever. The contribu on printed maps has had on all of the small town in North-East France, St. Dié, Waldseemüller would produce a aspects of European life are neatly intertwined. The intellectual interest for 31 32 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous geographical representa on created a market that thrived for innova on, which, in back four hundred years prior to the German’s existence. Furthermore, the turn, led to a significant influence on social norms and views of the wider world. innova ve idea to develop the technology into metal movable print arrived a Before this essay proceeds, it is fundamental to establish some context of cartography. In each field, one individual is thought to be the master: Virgin for poetry; Quin lian for teaching; and Aristotle for physics. For geography, the acknowledged authorita ve figure is Claudius Ptolemy (AD 97 – 150). The Alexandrian’s masterful work, Geographike Hyphegesis (‘Guide to Cartography’) contained the principles acceding to which the world maps might be drawn and boasted a vast catalogue of la tude and longitude co-ordinates for approximately eight thousand places in the known world.6 As soon as the manuscripts of Ptolemy and other geographers were rediscovered and arrived upon the fer le land of Europe, they proliferated, assumed an authority, and circulated within intellectual spheres. By 1409, the La n transla on of Ptolemy’s text had been finished by The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 genera on before Gutenberg, in Korea (the earliest metal type printed document is a Buddhist manuscript that dates at 1377).8 Nevertheless, upon its arrival in the 1450’s, the technology spread like wildfire and by the end of the fi eenth century, prin ng presses were established in all major ci es. Moveable type prin ng press expanded the capaci es of produc on to rates thought to be unimaginable beforehand. During the sixth and seventh centuries, produc on of books sat at roughly 120 per annum. In 1790 alone, twenty million books were bound.9 Similar pa ers were reflected in mapmaking. From 1476, 56,000 maps were said to be in circula on in Western Europe; geography began to become a commonality in everyday life. This growth con nued to flourish in the sixteenth century, of which by the end the number of maps in existence is said to be in the millions.10 Jacobus Angeli.7 Despite every major European city having the classical figure’s However, it would be fallible to assume that the advent of the prin ng press knowledge at their disposal, map circula on on the con nent was in its embryonic ini ated a pan-European advancement in geographic knowledge among the stages. Between 1400 and 1476, maps were s ll in their manuscript form and everyday person. In fact, the obsession with Classical An quity was exacerbated es mates stand at just a few thousand maps exis ng in Western Europe during this through the technology. As early as 1477, the first printed edi on of Geography me. appeared in Bologna, of which a thousand were printed – a sizeable scale However, Europe finally caught up with Asia and introduced the prin ng press into its opera ons. Contrary to popular opinion, Johannes Gutenberg did not develop moveable type print. Its inven on originates in China (c. 1040) and dates 33 considering the freshness of the technology (Figure 2). Seven different printed edi ons appeared by 1490 and over half of the maps printed before 1500 were Ptolemaic.11 Saying this, the prin ng press, as Eisenstein argued, created a ‘process 34 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous of feedback’ and ‘laid the basis for… modern science’.12 The technology had most cases, printed maps were more expensive than its manuscript form due to the enabled these classical texts to run loose on the wider European popula on. The requirement to employ individuals to color each map in rich colors. Saying this, diffusion of Ptolemaic maps and the mul plicity of edi ons bore witness to the geography in the sixteenth century was a thriving market. It did not take long for rapidity of the process of verifica on, correc on, and refinement. Indeed, as the printers, engravers, and cartographers to arrive at the realiza on that maps sixteenth century progressed, Ptolemaic edi ons were being consulted and possessed cultural, intellectual, but most importantly, financial value. Indeed, interpreted to incorporate new contemporary discoveries. The 1508 Rome edi on, Johannes Grüninger, one of the most influen al printers in Strasbourg encapsulated for example, included the most Southern part of Africa, showing the sea route to such commercial possibili es. In 1507, Grüninger printed one thousand copies of India that was inaugurated by Vasca Da Gama.13 Furthermore, the 1513 Strasburg Waldseemüller’s famous twelve-sheet wall map (men oned above) equa ng to a edi on juxtaposes twenty-seven maps by Ptolemy with twenty-five modern maps, print run of twelve thousand separate sheets. By 1525, Grüninger had printed no five of which are of Africa and Asia.14 Vying with one another in terms of accuracy, fewer than 3,500 wall maps composed of over 98,000 sheets.16 An endeavor of this detail, and novelty, each passing edi on grew recognizably more modern. The scale reflects the confidence in a healthy market for beau fully illustrated and Ptolemaic outlook on the world began to be increasingly viewed as the ves ge of a expensive maps. However, this growing market brought about more than just past civiliza on. Such a feeling is symbolized in Mercator’s 1577 produc on that prosperity to the cartographic industry. The establishment of such a widening consisted of original Ptolemaic maps, free of any correc ons or moderniza ons – community of readers ignited a shi in the nature of which these maps could be almost a novelty work.15 In essence, print culture’s uniformity and absence of produced. This imagined community, that was beginning to base their geographical varia on in its produc on fed and promoted a growing interest in geography knowledge on the printed maps, allowed for geographers to distance themselves among the wider intellectual circles. The European mind – broadened by Ptolemy – from patrons. Indeed, as the market began to gear itself towards the increasingly began to stretch beyond familiar shores and seas. Reawakened Europe was heading anonymous public, mapmakers were now encouraged to travel to the major inexorably towards an en cing future. commercial ci es of Europe in search for possible exchanges between colleagues in The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 the form of informa on and knowledge.17 As a result, Europeans were now able to With the exponen al rise in the volume of maps, one would expect that the benefit from a growing diversifica on of geographical representa on rather than a price would fall, as is the case with books, however, this is not the case. Instead, in 35 36 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal biased outlook of the world according to a wealthy commissioner. However, the increase in circula on of maps did not come without problems. They were a vital asset to every man whose business was foreign commerce yet a nuisance to handle. Aegidius Hoo man, a canny merchant from Antwerp, was one of many who grumbled about the logis cal inconvenience of printed maps. It is within these condi ons that allowed for one of the greatest figures in cartographical history to flourish: Abraham Ortelius, a Flemish cartographer and geographer. Ortelius began to develop a scheme to write the Harry Sophocleous The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 was not Theatrum’s only significance. In the closing words of the atlas, Ortelius wrote: ‘in these Tables themselves, a certain Shoppe, as it were, furnished with all hide of instruments necessarily required in such like business’.19 The juxtaposi on of the atlas to a shop neutralizes its presence as an indispensible part of the social and poli cal life of the elites that was free from any poli cal par ality. The prin ng press created the intellectual and commercial possibility for Ortelius to realize that their output would be more commercially successful and intellectually respected if it distracted itself from the poli cally or aristocra c bias. rapidly growing body of regional and global knowledge into one volume: an atlas. Furthermore, it is with the opening of this mass market that allowed this On May 20th, 1570, the first modern geographical atlas was issued, bearing the period to be dis nguished as a winning combina on of geographical accuracy with name: Theatrum Orbis Terrarum (‘Theatre of the World’). The atlas consisted of 35 rich ornamenta on. To think, as Jerry Bro on does, that geography transformed leaves of text, 53 maps, and a catalogue of geographers and cartographers who ‘itself from a mysterious art into a scien fically exact field of poli cal and contributed. It was a universal, commercial, and intellectual success. The ini al print commercial administra on’ would be a naïve asser on.20 Due to mainstream sold so well that a second edi on was printed soon a er. By the end of 1570, geographical knowledge tangled up in close-knit connec ons between European another four edi ons had been printed; the following year, a Dutch edi on had city-states, mapmakers began to alter their cartographical ornamental to a ract appeared. Year by year the Theatrum grew in size, and, by 1612, there were no wider appeal. Geographic maps, atlases, and tle pages were now looking from a fewer than 42 edi ons in circula on, translated into every major European collec ve European perspec ve to demarcate countries, regions, and even language.18 con nents. As a result, depic ons of geographical imagery that is coupled with Ortelius achieved his aim to condense the diversity of both classical and contemporary forms of geographical knowledge into a single volume, from which its owners could extract the informa on they required in an instant. However, this 37 allegorical allusions and historical connec ons broke new ground in providing a more impressive introduc on to a printed work than the preceding printer’s simple colophon.21 38 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 A form of this intellectually created geographical sphere began in Ortelius’s on the con nent began to have an influence on the way they viewed the world. The tle page for his 1570 atlas, Theatrum Orbis Terrarum, in which a personifica on of promo on of Chris anity and European supremacy would manage to drown out any the four known con nents contained allegorical connota ons (Figure 3). Upon a first feelings of inferiority for foreign races when looking at the known world as a whole. glance at the image, it is apparent to any spectator that Europe is the most Any drawbacks that the alterna ve races may have had was not viewed to be their commanding of the four. Indeed, she is depicted as the empress of the world, si ng individual faults, but simply because they were not European. Indeed, it is possible at an elevated level, gripping a specter in her right hand, and with her le , holding a that William Strachey had this reinforced concep on of European supremacy in mind rudder in the shape of a Chris an cross, controlling the course in which the world when he arrived in the New World in the early seventeenth century. He wrote a takes. On the other hand, Africa is scan ly clad, with just enough to cover her loins. poem to describe his experience of an Indian dance, thus crea ng an insight into a Rays of the sun wrap around her head to form a nature casque and a spiky halo. European’s first impressions when they encountered new beings from obscure Furthermore, she is holding a sprig of balsam, of which its unique provenance is corners of the globe: Egypt – this may well be an act of homage.22 This innova ve crea on influenced ‘Wild as there are, accept them, so were we many decora ve and allegorical fron spieces for numerous atlases and world maps over the next 150 years. Indeed, the tle page for Hondius-Mercator’s atlas of 1623 exuded similar characteris cs (Figure 4). One again, Europe was depicted as the crown for the world, clutching a specter while simultaneously holding a floral cornucopia – a reminder that her ruling authority produces peace and plenty. With Africa, once again, an emphasis was placed on the sun, with the black female a emp ng to shield herself with an umbrella, whilst wielding an umbrella and mounted on a large crocodile – a reference to the primi ve nature of the African To make them civil, will our honour be And if good words, be the effects of Myndes Which like good Angels be, let our Designs.’24 It’s clear that the atlases contributed to a growing feeling of European supremacy when it came to dealing with other races during the ‘Age of Discovery’. Indeed, maps did not create this feeling of European supremacy, but it was instrumental in strengthening the regulari es of foreign lands and restric ng any xenophobic feeling that may have been festering beforehand. For example, the 23 civiliza on. element of the sun appearing in both depic ons of Africa is a reference to the The success of these European atlases among the wider intellectual spheres 39 misadventures of Phaeton, the son of the ancient Greek god of sun. 40 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous This associa on with the classical world is a clear acceptance of some form of human civiliza on in Africa, albeit if they think it is of a low standard.25 The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 Saying this, the prin ng press allowed for map ownership among the upper echelons of European society to surge. This made possible the assimila on of a Saying this, there is a reason why this essay has adopted the term wholly new type of spa al awareness and a vastly more ambi ous sense of space. ‘mainstream’ when discussing geographic knowledge in Renaissance Europe. The Ortelius inexorably redefined the social status of early modern geography as a effects of print culture did not translate into any noteworthy breakthrough in the discipline that revolves around the demands of the market. While this did not geographic representa on of the world. There was a paradoxical gap between completely erase the poli cal element to maps, it undoubtedly forced a shi that manuscript maps – kept secret by merchants, monarchs and aristocrats for their saw the emergence of a more recognizable modern discipline.28 Without the accuracy and their subsequent commercial and poli cal value – and printed maps, of advent of the prin ng press, geography would have not have entered the mindset of which the informa on remained twenty or thirty years behind and had been built the mass public and the average European would have con nued to live in a world upon the founda on of inaccurate classical an qui es.26 Indeed, portolan charts that of darkness, oblivious to the scale of the lands of which he resides. With the originated in the Mediterranean Sea in the twel h century offered a remarkable intellectual spheres now excited by the no on of geography, European expansion accurate survey of various coastlines. These charts would have been func onal was now able to implement a new dimension to its adventures. The mo va on to instruments in the art of travel rather than an intellectual extravagance that could be map new journeys and to establish close rela onships between European ci es was sold for its ornamental value. As seen with the Portuguese world map of 1502, all in a empt to sa sfy a new pulsa ng market. Notes mariners would extract important detail from the map concerning various ports 1. F. Thackeray (ed), Events that Formed Modern World (London: ABC-CLIO, 2012), p. 188. 2. R. Stefoff, The Bri sh Library Companion to Maps and Mapmaking (London: Bri sh Library, 1995), p. 6. 3. J. Bro on, A History of the World in Twelve Maps (London: Penguin, 2013), p. 157. spread of prin ng only had a marginal effect in regards to the intellectual limits of 4. J. Wilford, The Mapmakers: The Story of the Great Pioneers in Cartography (London: Pimlico, 2002), pp. 84-5. European’s and their knowledge of the world. Print culture were only able to 5. E. Eisenstein, The Prin ng Press as an Agent of Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980).A. Johns, The Nature of the Book (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998). For an overview of historiography, read: A. Gra on, ‘How Revolu onary was the Print Revolu on?’, The American Historical Journal, vol. 107 (2002), pp. 84-6. 6. D. Buisseret, The Map Maker’s Quest (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 1216. along the coastlines, as well as the local powers that rule and would allow them to undertake diploma c and commercial missions (Figure 5).27 In other words, the contribute to developments that had come long before the efflorescence of printed maps in the sixteenth century. 41 42 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous Notes The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 Bibliography 7. C. Jacob, The Sovereign Map: Theore cal Approaches in Cartography throughout History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006), p. 54. Secondary literature 8. Manchester University, ‘Moveable Type Print’, h p://www.library.manchester.ac.uk/ firs mpressions/From-Manuscript-to-Print/Technology-of-the-Book/Movable-metaltype/ [Accessed 8th December 2014]. Barber, P., The Map Book (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 2005). 9. E. Buringh, ‘Char ng the “Rise of the West”: Manuscripts and Printed Books in Europe, a Long-Term Perspec ve from the Sixth through Eighteenth Centuries’, The Journal of Economic History, Vol. 69 (2009), pp. 409-445 (p.439). Binding, P., Imagined Corners: Exploring the World’s First Atlas (London: Headline Book Publishing, 2003). Bro on, J., A History of the World in Twelve Maps (London: Penguin, 2013). 10. D. Woodward, The History of Cartography, vol.3, pt.1 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007), p. 11. Bro on, J., Trading Territories: Mapping the Early Modern World (London: Reak on, 1997). 11. R. Unger, Ships on Maps: Pictures of Power in Renaissance Europe (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), pp. 62-70. Brown, L., The Story of Maps (London: Cresset Press, 1951). 12. Eisenstein, The Prin ng Press, pp. 479,704. 13. R. Tooley, Maps and Map-Makers (London: B. T. Batsford, 1970), pp. 6-7. 14. Jacob, The Sovereign Map, pp. 61-2. 15. Ibid. 16. H. Johnson, Carta Marina: World Geography in Strassburg (Minnesota: 1963), p. 124. Eisenstein, E., The Prin ng Press as an Agent of Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980). 17. J. Bro on, Trading Territories: Mapping the Early Modern World (London: Reak on, 1997), pp. 169-77. Gra on, A., ‘How Revolu onary was the Print Revolu on?’, The American Historical Journal, vol. 107 (2002). 18. L. Brown, The Story of Maps (London: Cresset Press, 1951), pp. 160-4. 19. Bro on, Trading Territories, pp. 169-77. 20. Ibid. 21. R. Shirley, ‘The Title Pages to the Theatrum and Parergon’ in M. van den Broecke, P. van der Krogt, and P. Meurer, Abraham Ortelius and the First Atlas (Utrecht: HES Publishers, 1998), pp. 161-4. Buisseret, D., The Map Maker’s Quest (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003). Buringh, E., ‘Char ng the “Rise of the West”: Manuscripts and Printed Books in Europe, a Long -Term Perspec ve from the Sixth through Eighteenth Centuries’, The Journal of Economic History, Vol. 69 (2009). Jacob, C., The Sovereign Map: Theore cal Approaches in Cartography throughout History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006). Johns, A., The Nature of the Book (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998). Johnson, H., Carta Marina: World Geography in Strassburg (Minnesota: 1963). 22. P. Binding, Imagined Corners: Exploring the World’s First Atlas (London: Headline Book Publishing, 2003), pp. 209-214. 23. P. Barber, The Map Book (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 2005), pp. 154-5. 24. W. Strachey, The First Booke of the Historie of Travaile into Virginia Britannica (161012). 25. Binding, Imagined Corners, pp. 209-14. 26. Jacob, The Sovereign Map, pp. 54-66. 27. Buisseret, The Mapmakers’ Quest, p. 71. Thackeray, F. (ed), Events that Formed Modern World (London: ABC-CLIO, 2012). 28. Bro on, Trading Territories, pp. 176-7. Tooley, R., Maps and Map-Makers (London: B. T. Batsford, 1970). 43 Shirley, R., ‘The Title Pages to the Theatrum and Parergon’ in M. van den Broecke, P. van der Krogt, and P. Meurer, Abraham Ortelius and the First Atlas (Utrecht: HES Publishers, 1998). Stefoff, R., The Bri sh Library Companion to Maps and Mapmaking (London: Bri sh Library, 1995). Strachey, W., The First Booke of the Historie of Travaile into Virginia Britannica (London: Bri sh Library, 1610-12). 44 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Bibliography Harry Sophocleous The prin ng of maps in Europe between 1450 and 1650 Figure collection Secondary literature Unger, R., Ships on Maps: Pictures of Power in Renaissance Europe (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010). Wilford, J., The Mapmakers: The Story of the Great Pioneers in Cartography (London: Pimlico, 2002). Woodward, D., The History of Cartography, vol.3, pt.1 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2007). Primary literature Manchester University, ‘Moveable Type Print’, h p://www.library.manchester.ac.uk/ firs mpressions/From-Manuscript-to-Print/Technology-of-the-Book/Movable-metal-type/ [Accessed 8th December 2014]. Figure 2: Bri sh Library, London, Claudius Ptolemy, 'Geographia', 1477. Figure collection Figure 1: Library of Congress, Washington D.C., Mar n Waldseemüller, ‘Universalis Cosmographia’, 1507. Figure 3: Boston Public Library, Abraham Ortelius, 'Theatrum Orbis Terrarum', 1570: Title Page. 45 46 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe Tribal iden es in African States Figure collection ‘Identity is a knife’: Must tribal identities be repressed in order for African States to avoid internal violent conflict? Sebas an Lowe Iden ty in Africa is an issue that, from the outside, is usually portrayed as primordial and intractable. This gives rise to the impression that there is nothing to be done, except perhaps suppress such tribal iden fluid history of tribal iden es en rely. But by analysing the es it becomes clear that the issue moves beyond mere tribalism. O en Tribal conflicts in Africa emerge out of a crisis of ci zenship and Figure 4: Private Collec on, Hondius-Mercator, 'Africa', 1623. representa on that challenges the post-colonial state system. The tribes themselves emerge from the frozen, primordial culture in which they are cast and take their true, fluid and dynamic forms. While there are myriad examples of tribal conflict across the Con nent this analysis will focus on the issue within the Great Lakes region of Central Africa; specifically Rwanda, Burundi, and the eastern regions of the Democra c Republic of Congo (DRC). To realis cally comprehend how Tribalism is understood by communi es in Africa today a be er understanding of their complex history is needed. O en tribal Figure 5: Bibloteca Estense Universitaria Moderna: Anonymous Portuguese World Map, 1502. conflicts are seen as eternal by outsiders; while others dismiss such grievances as an en rely colonial inven on. The truth is far more nuanced than this, and the tribes of the great lakes provide strong evidence of this. The most significant ethnic cleavage in the region is the infamous dis nc on between Hutu and Tutsi. 47 48 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe These (along with the Twa) form the three largest ethnic groups in both Rwanda and conflict back into the primordial past. What this shows is that tribal iden Burundi. Some have dismissed them as a colonial inven on but there is clear pre-colonial era were rela vely peaceful, a context which can not be disregarded in evidence that these two groups existed in the region for centuries. However in the favour of the total suppression of tribes. Tribal iden es in African States es in the historic Kingdoms of Burundi and Rwanda the dis nc on was far more fluid than But establishing tribal iden ty as being neither fixed and primordial nor a today. It is o en described as akin to a class division, with the Hutu majority o en colonial inven on is not to discount the transforma ve effect colonialism had on subservient to the ruling Tutsi elite: and it was possible for a Hutu to "become" a Iden ty in Africa. The policy of "Indirect Rule" saw the colonial regimes' legi macy Tutsi. There is li le evidence of ethnic conflict between the two groups, conflict was secured through gaining the loyalty of tribal "chiefs". Regimes argued the policy more inter-elite; and while the Tutsi elite were no ceably taller than the Hutu protected indigenous culture but Ronald Aminzade contends that o en officials peasant class there was li le biological difference. In fact, in Southern Rwanda the devoted substan al energy to finding chiefs even when they knew that no such Tutsi farmers were indis nguishable from their Hutu neighbours. 1 2 figure existed.4 Where Rwanda and Burundi saw ethnicity created out of a typical The more dynamic tribal region of what was to become the eastern DRC was more complex than the centralised kingdoms to the east, but iden ty was s ll clearly a fluid concept. The groups that inhabited this region had li le fixed iden ty as tribes, but iden ty was s ll present. The Congolese historical tradi on was centred around three strata of the house, village and the district. While these communi es, to varying degrees, shared a common language and culture they were organised primarily for defence and thus there was no poli cal centralisa on or permanent process of indirect rule Bogumil Jewsiewicki sees iden ty in the Congo come from a push towards regionalism. By drawing "reality out of fic on" the crea on of a state-wide na onal space depended ini ally on developing regional es. Regionalism saw the crea on of "ethnici es" out of hitherto similar cultural spheres, for example the crea on of a "Luba" iden ty out of an area that shared similar dialects. Moreover regionalism saw the crea on of a feared internal enemy (a "Stranger"), be it the Luba in Kasai or the Kinyarwandese in the Kivus. A comparison can be made to the Jewish "internal enemy" that has historically existed in Europe.5 In the eastern country the authority.3 Kinyarwandan popula on in North Kivu was swelled by the forced migra on of up to What these pre-colonial iden es show is that tribal iden ty has not always 300,000 Rwandese throughout the colonial period.6 This process formalized and been the divisive, rigid structure that one finds today, and to say that the rivalries fixed iden between the tribes of the great lakes region are intractable is to project the present 49 authority to tribal chiefs and tying people to the land of their tribe. 50 es that had previously been largely fluid, serving to both centralize Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe This type of colonial rule was not unique, but the Belgian regime were ardent with the arrangement of power prior to colonial rule, where power was organised enforcers of it. The a ermath of the first World War saw the crea on of mandates primarily around defence and permanent authority over villages, or even individual which the League of Na ons defined as "peoples not yet able to stand by themselves houses, was uncommon.11 Crawford Young says it is not coincidence that under the strenuous condi ons of the modern world." But in principle this was an colonialism in Africa "coincided with the historical zenith of virulent racism" and that extension of the Belgian empire which had ruled Congo for the previous three the postcolonial states s ll feel the effects of this.12 But while the colonial regimes decades. Ironically the mandate periods were o en jus fied as a defense against the were clearly racially prejudiced this cannot be seen to con nue unchanged, to argue "Tribal divisions" that were a consequence of indirect rule.7 The former German this is to again cast iden ty as sta c and primordial. Rather Mamdani's case that regime had made extensive use of the Hutu-Tutsi divide. By co-op ng the Tutsi to what the colonial regime did was create a "bifurcated state" where ci zenship was rule over the Hutu the German Empire had managed to rule Ruanda-Urundi with a granted to "civilised" men and en re groups were excluded because of their minute number of personnel. The Tutsis themselves took advantage of their ethnicity, has far more relevance for the post-colonial states today.13 From this privileged posi on and there are cases of them even collec ng taxes in areas outside bifurca on one can see how the exclusion of groups during the colonial regime of German control.8 The incoming Belgian regime took these divide and rule tac cs began a crisis of ci zenship, of who was within the state and who was outside it; and es through id cards, introduced in 1933-34.9 The iden ty's fluidity, rather than primordial racism, makes such a crisis highly further by fixing the iden arguments used by the Belgian Empire extensively employed the fashionable Tribal iden es in African States combus ble. rhetoric of race science. O en this resulted in the crea on of origin myths; the most infamous of these was the "Hami c hypothesis" which contented that the Tutsi were not na ve to the region, nor even a Bantu tribe, but were a superior and more civilized tribe who had descended from the Nile region to the north.10 What such myths did was exclude the Hutu from most aspects of public life on racial grounds, while simultaneously fostering resentment towards the "invading" Tutsi elite. Jan Vansina has shown that the power granted to chiefs was en rely at odds In describing Sierra Leone's civil war Paul Richards saw violence as discourse and war as text: "a violent a empt to... 'cut in on the conversa on' of others from whose company the belligerents feel excluded."14 This concept crystallises the logic of tribal violence not as a primal hatred but ins tu onalised exclusion. Rene Lemarchand finds this idea as central to explaining the Hutu-Tutsi animosity in the post colonial period; and the fact that the 1972 Burundian genocide of Hutu by Tutsi has been largely forgo en is telling. Between April-November, 1972, 100-200,000 51 52 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe Hutus were exterminated by the Burundian-Tutsi regime, and Lemarchand sees this incorporated into the state.18 Morten Bøås expands this idea to a con nental issue context as crucial to subsequent Hutu-Tutsi rela ons. It significantly contextualises which he defines as "autochthony". He sees the European no on of ci zenship the seizure of power by Hutus in Rwanda in 1973 under Juvenal Habyarimana.15 Liisa within a civil society as unravelling across post-colonial Africa, as different groups Malkki also sees the subsequent refusal to incorporate Hutus into the Burundian claim "autochthonous", inalienable rights to the land. The groups iden fied as out- state as fundamental to the radicalisa on of the Hutu refugees in Tanzania and the siders are more than just Mamdani's "strangers" but are in essence denied forma on of the PALIPEHUTU movement. That this movement would destabilise ci zenship. Bøås sees the Eastern DRC to be a prime example of this language of Burundi to such a degree in 1993 is a direct consequence of the ability of the Hutu autochthony for while the Congolese 1964 Cons tu on grants that there is "only one ethnicity to give a "mythico-history" to what in other contexts would be a poli cal Congolese na onality" the fact individuals had to prove ancestry da ng back to 1908 iden ty.16 Both Lemarchand and Malkki concur that the ethnically driven poli cal meant that ci zenship was ed to the land.19 For Stephen Jackson this dialogue exclusion has a dis nct toxicity, and it becomes clear that the living memory of ethnic between the "Strangers" and the "sons of the soil" is not present in the longue durée violence explains the violent reac on of Hutus upon hearing that the first Hutu but a consequence of the colonial fixing of iden ty and the crea on of homelands president of Burundi, Ndadaye, had been assassinated. The Hutu refugees who fled (the same process of regionalism outlined by Jewsiewicki).20 Tribal iden es in African States into Rwanda at this point needed li le encouragement to join the Hutu mili a.17 Throughout the post-independence period the ques on of which groups Lemarchand is prescient when arguing that the forma on of a collec ve belonged to the land was central: from 1972 the influen al Congolese Tutsi poli cian memory and mythology marks ethnic violence as dis nct and more likely to escalate Barthélemy Bisengimana changed the law on ci zenship to those living in Congo but this iden fies a symptom rather than a cause. The dis nct dynamics of the prior to 1950; but this was changed again when leaders of the "autochthonous" Hutu-Tutsi myth exemplify the fundamental issue that defined the post-colonial Babembe tribe from south Kivu pushed the date back to the Berlin Conference of regimes. 1885.21 As shall be shown below this conflict is s ll not resolved, but by connec ng Returning to the origin myth and the Hame c hypothesis, Mamdani sees the the language of autochthony with Mamdani's crisis of ci zenship one sees it as less a ethnic violence as fundamentally a "Crisis of ci zenship", by which the ethnic conflict over historical tribal differences and more a recent ques on over what "Stranger" status of the Tutsi is projected onto the more fundamental issue of who is cons tutes the post-colonial state. 53 54 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe By viewing the tribal iden es not as fixed and historic but recent and fluid, and by like Kangura pushed many in the Hutu community towards violence.27 The viewing the post-independence conflict as more over ci zenship and autochthony assassina on of President Habyarimana began the orchestrated execu on of at least than primordial hatred, the most dis nct period of violence in the region through half the Rwandan Tutsi popula on over the course of 100 days.28 But what must be the 1990s is no longer seen as incomprehensible, tribal chaos but as a crisis of stressed is that the Hutu genocidaires were not mo vated by pure hatred but by the statehood grounded in a dis nct logic. The region's first violent outbreak in the dual crises of immanent military defeat by the RPF29 and the memory of violence 1990s was not in Rwanda but in Burundi. Under pressure from interna onal donors against Hutus in 1972.30 In this sense the genocidaires chose to "embrace death itself the Tutsi minority government of Pierre Buyoya held the first democra c elec ons. as an alterna ve to life without power".31 Tribal iden es in African States But the Buyoya government was shocked by the elec on of a moderate Hutu, Melchior Ndadye.22 More than a tribal rivalry, the Tutsi government feared that The violence against the Tutsi only ended once the RPF had seized power and pushed the Hutu genocidaires, along with 2 million Hutu refugees, into neighbouring Ndadye's elec on would see their removal from civil society, as the Hutu's held an Zaire (Congo).32 But the RPF's victory did li le to fundamentally alter ethnic 85% majority and their diaspora movement had increased the autochthonous rhetoric within the Hutu community since 1972.23 24 The violent coup launched by dynamics in the region. Infused with their own mythology and ideology the RPF ensured that they were central to the forma on of the state, and moreover, as the Tutsi military, and Buyoya's assassina on in October 1993, are seen by Reyntjens has discussed at length, excluded the remaining Hutu from full poli cal Lemarchand as another example of trying to "cut in on the conversa on" of the par cipa on.33 This ideology helps one understand why the "counter-genocide" of 25 Hutu Frodbeu party. the Hutu by the RPF was not only unreported but deemed acceptable34, for the RPF's In 1994 the Hutu government of Rwanda also feared they were about to be constella on of morality firmly entrenched the Tutsi as the permanent vic ms just as excluded from the conversa on. Interna onal pressure to pluralise and the Tutsi the exiled Burundian Hutu in Tanzania had cast themselves decades earlier.35 This invasion of the Rwandan Patrio c Front (RPF) from neighbouring Uganda had led the also contextualises why the violence was so rapidly exported across the border to Habyarimana regime to fear expulsion from the process of government.26 Key to the the Eastern DRC; not only did the RPF leader Paul Kagame sponsor the rebel "Hutu Power" ideology was the claim the Tutsi were an alien race come to movement that toppled Congo's entrenched dictator Mobutu, but then launched a reconquer the land, and poli cal broadcasts over the radio RTKM and in newspapers seven year proxy war that saw Rwanda gain effec ve control over large swathes of 55 56 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe Congolese territory. It has been claimed that this occupa on was largely for control the poli cal par cipa on of other minori es. When wri ng of the Batwa community of resources but what cannot be ignored is Kagame's desire for the Hutu Refugees Danielle Beswick has described how they have no representa on in the state; and (now the rebel FDLR movement) to permanently remain genocidaires outside the the Rwandan Ministry of Jus ce threatened to stop all NGO projects within the country, rather than to return as a poli cal majority and, once again, a empt to Batwa community if they con nued to be referred to as a dis nct ethnic minority.39 remove the Tutsi from civil society.36 In this way the suppression of iden ty in no way incorporates the ethnic groups into By analysing the cycles of blame and violence that occurred through the postcolonial period one is drawn to the social science concept of "retribu ve Tribal iden es in African States the state; and the collec ve memory that ethnic conflict creates ensures that a return to violence remains a dis nct possibility. genocide" developed by Vahakn Dadrian and Helen Fein. Across all three countries But calls to abandon repression are o en accompanied with pressure on discussed it was the stra fied state machinery that saw one group suppress another, governments to liberalise and pluralise; which can also result in internal conflict. It which feeds the mythology of the suppressed and makes them more opposed to was precisely the pressure on the Habyarimana and Buyoya governments to a empts at inclusion.37 In this sense ethnic exclusion, with its propensity for liberalise and pluralise that frightened the extremist elite to s r up ethnic hatred and collec ve memory and a single "truth", is more pernicious than any other commit to a genocide. Democra sa on is likely to create ethnic conflict in countries stra fica on; but as the case studies above show it is the fundamental issue of with "a popula on with poor civic and underdeveloped representa ve and ci zenship and a fear of being removed from civil society that drives ethnic divisions journalis c ins tu ons; and elites who are threatened with democra c change". This to such violent conflicts. is especially so in countries who s ll bear the legacies of colonial ethnic divisions.40 It becomes clear that suppression does not in any way baddress the fundamental issues. In Rwanda ethnic iden fica on has been suppressed, and there Instead a long period of developing ins tu ons must first lay the groundwork for democra sa on that does not produce ethnic violence. is a strict bar on any form of ethnic poli cs. But this has had the adverse affect of When describing iden ty as a knife Helen Hintjens makes the dis nc on that excluding Hutu from the poli cal process as they themselves have to iden fy with iden ty is not a knife, but rather becomes one.41 This may be a fundamental point the RPF's official truth; any a empt to do otherwise is punishable as "Genocide when arguing against the mere suppression of tribal iden ideology.”38 Moreover denying any form of iden ty poli cs has extremely hindered knife when the fluid nature of it became fixed; when the colonial state became a 57 es. Iden ty became a bifurcated one; when the post-colonial state sees the ques on of ci zenship 58 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe transform into an issue of autochthony; and when the collec ve memory and Tribal iden es in African States Notes mythology iden fies one group as perennial vic ms, and the other as the sole 16. Malkki, L.H. Purity in Exile: Violence, Memory and Na onal Cosmology among Hutu Refugees in Tanzania, (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1995), pp. 36-25. perpetrators of violence. In this context merely suppressing iden ty does not 17. Lemarchand, R. "Genocide in the Great Lakes: Which Genocide? Whose Genocide?", African Studies Review, 41:1 (April, 1998), p. 6. 18. Mamdani, (2001), pp. 234-236. 19. Bøås, M. "Autochthony and Ci zenship: 'Civil Society' as Vernacular Architecture" Journal of Interven on and Statebuilding, 6:1 (April, 2012), p. 98. 20. Jackson, S "Sons of Which Soil? The Language and Poli cs of Autochthony in Eastern D.R. Congo", African Studies Review, 49:2 (September, 2006), p. 98. 21. Bøås, (2012), p. 98. 22. Snyder, J. (2000) From Vo ng to Violence: Democra sa on and Na onalist Conflict, (W.W. Norton & Co., New York, US), p. 300. 23. Ibid. 24. Malkki, (1995), p. 250. 25. Lemarchand, (1998), p.11. 26. Klinghoffer, A.J. The Interna onal Dimension of Genocide in Rwanda, (Macmillan, London, 1998), p. 17. address the fundamental issue of crea ng a pluralis c state; something that is urgently needed to defuse the "simmering volcano before it blows up yet again, this me engulfing the wider region."42 Notes 1. Dunn, K.C. Imagining the Congo: the Interna onal Rela ons of Iden ty, (Palgrave Macmillan, New York, 2003), pp. 148-152. 2. Mamdani, M. When Vic ms Become Killers: Colonialism, Na vism and the Genocide in Rwanda (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2001), pp. 41-74. 3. Vansina, J. Paths in the Rainforest: Towards a History of Poli cal Tradi on in Equatorial Africa, (University of Wisconsin, Madison, 1990), pp. 70-80. 4. Aminzade, R. Race, Na on, and Ci zenship in Post-Colonial Africa, (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2013), p. 39. 27. Mamdani, (2001), p. 190. 5. Jewsiewicki "The Forma on of the Poli cal Culture of Ethnicity in the Belgian Congo: 1920-1959" in Vail, L. (ed). The Crea on of Tribalism in Southern Africa, (University of California Press, Berkely, 1991), pp. 327-330. 28. Klinghoffer, (1998), p. 3. 29. Mamdani, (2001), p. 215. 6. Huggins, C "Land, Power and Iden ty: The Roots of Violence in Eastern DRC", Interna onal Alert, (November, 2010), p. 16. 30. Lemarchand, (1998), p. 7. 31. Mamdani, (2001), p. 215. 7. Aminzade, (2013), pp. 37-39. 32. 8. Louis, R,W.M. Ruanda-Urundi: 1884-1919, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1963), p. 158. Prunier, G Africa's World War: Congo, the Rwandan Genocide, and the Making of a Con nental Catastrophe, (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009), pp. 4-5. 9. Dunn, (2003), p. 148. 33. Find in Reyntjens. 10. Louis, (1963), pp. 107-08. 34. Lemarchand, (1998), p. 8. 11. Vansina, (1990), pp. 70-80. 35. Malkki, (1995), p. 250. 12. Young, C. The African Colonial State in Compara ve Perspec ve, (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1994), p. 280. 36. Autesserre, S. The Trouble With the Congo: Local Violence and the Failure of Interna onal Peacebuilding, (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2010), p. 61. 13. Mamdani, M. Ci zen and Subject: Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late Colonialism, (Fountain, Kampala, 1996), pp. 16-18. 37. Klinghoffer, (1998), p.115. 38. Mamdani, (2001), p. 270. 14. Richards, P. Figh ng for the Rainforest: War, Youth & Resources in Sierra Leone (Villiers, London, 1996), p. xxiv. 39. Beswick, D. "Democracy, Iden ty and the Poli cs of Exclusion in Post-Genocide Rwanda: The Case of the Batwa", Democra za on, 18:02 (April, 2011), p. 502. 15. Lemarchand, R. "Genocide in the Great Lakes: Which Genocide? Whose Genocide?", African Studies Review, 41:1 (April, 1998), pp. 5-7. 40. Snyder, (2000), pp. 296-306. 59 60 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sebas an Lowe Notes 41. Hintjens, H. "When Iden ty Becomes a Knife: Reflec ng on the Genocide in Rwanda" Ethnici es, 1:1 (April, 2001), p. 26. 42. Mamdani, (2001), p. 215. Bibliography Tribal iden es in African States Bibliography Secondary literature Richards, P. Figh ng for the Rainforest: War, Youth & Resources in Sierra Leone, (Villiers, London, 1996). Snyder, J. (2000) From Vo ng to Violence: Democra sa on and Na onalist Conflict, (W.W. Norton & Co., New York, US). Vansina, J. Paths in the Rainforest: Towards a History of Poli cal Tradi on in Equatorial Africa, (University of Wisconsin, Madison, 1990). Secondary literature Aminzade, R. Race, Na on, and Ci zenship in Post-Colonial Africa. [Online]. (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2013). Available from: Cambridge Books Online h p:// dx.doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107360259 [Accessed 17 December 2014]. Young, C. The African Colonial State in Compara ve Perspec ve, (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1994). Autesserre, S. The Trouble With the Congo: Local Violence and the Failure of Interna onal Peacebuilding, (Cambridge University Press, New York, 2010). Beswick, D. "Democracy, Iden ty and the Poli cs of Exclusion in Post-Genocide Rwanda: The Case of the Batwa" Democra za on, 18:02 (April, 2011). Bøås, M. "Autochthony and Ci zenship: 'Civil Society' as Vernacular Architecture" Journal of Interven on and Statebuilding, 6:1 (April, 2012). Dunn, K.C. Imagining the Congo: the Interna onal Rela ons of Iden ty, (Palgrave Macmillan, New York, 2003). Huggins, C "Land, Power and Iden ty: The Roots of Violence in Eastern DRC", Interna onal Alert, (November, 2010). Hintjens, H. "When Iden ty Becomes a Knife: Reflec ng on the Genocide in Rwanda", Ethnici es, 1:1 (April, 2001). Jackson, S "Sons of Which Soil? The Language and Poli cs of Autochthony in Eastern D.R. Congo", African Studies Review, 49:2 (September, 2006). Jewsiewicki "The Forma on of the Poli cal Culture of Ethnicity in the Belgian Congo: 19201959" in Vail, L. (ed). The Crea on of Tribalism in Southern Africa, (University of California Press, Berkely, 1991). Klinghoffer, A.J. The Interna onal Dimension of Genocide in Rwanda, (Macmillan, London, 1998). Lemarchand, R. "Genocide in the Great Lakes: Which Genocide? Whose Genocide?", African Studies Review, 41:1 (April, 1998). Louis, R,W.M. Ruanda-Urundi: 1884-1919, (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1963). Malkki, L.H. Purity in Exile: Violence, Memory and Na onal Cosmology among Hutu Refugees in Tanzania, (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1995). Mamdani, M. Ci zen and Subject: Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of Late Colonialism, (Fountain, Kampala, 1996). Mamdani, M. When Vic ms Become Killers: Colonialism, Na vism and the Genocide in Rwanda, (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2001). 61 62 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sam Allen Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill In analysing these differences several key tenants of Mill and Bentham’s Analyse the main differences between the utilitarianism of thought shall be examined in detail. First, Bentham’s ‘quan ta ve hedonism’ will be compared to Mill’s ‘qualita ve’ concep on of happiness. This will lead onto a Jeremy Bentham and that of John Stuart Mill considera on of how Bentham’s views of human mo va on and self-interest Sam Allen contrasted with Mill and his theory of life and how these differences informed their The moral theory of u litarianism is built upon the premise that the maximising of human happiness or ‘u lity’ is the moral index for which ac ons should be evaluated and judged. Hence, the consequen alist theory places u lity at the founda on of morality, and seeks to reject a priori formula ons of intrinsic value in ac ons.1 Having weathered severe cri cism since its emergence in the eighteenth century, the modern u litarian school now stands as one of the most important ethical frameworks in moral and poli cal philosophy. This essay will examine the main differences between the ideas of two of its greatest contributors; Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and his protégé John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). I will analyse varying poli cal views on the nature and role of government within a u litarian context. Indeed, the role of the legislator in Bentham’s cons tu onal model will be compared to Mill’s concep on of individuals as moral agents of u lity. Acutely conscious of his tutor’s cri cs, Mill’s work undoubtedly departs from Bentham’s ideas in significant ways. Yet, rather than looking to discredit Bentham’s ideas, it will be maintained that Mill seeks to provide a defence of Bentham’s u litarianism that works to make the “greatest happiness” principle a more encompassing and nuanced theory. In this sense, it will be suggested that a reading of Mill’s ideas can inform a re-interpreta on of Bentham’s u litarian thought. Bentham’s u litarianism through the prism of Mill’s significant refinements, and will Jeremy Bentham and J. S. Mill both seek to prove that the moral value of seek to prove that their differing theories stem from their contras ng concep ons of ac ons are con ngent upon the human happiness they bring about. Indeed, both human psychology and sociability. Indeed, Bentham’s more simple and reduc ve place happiness as the founda on of morality because the seeking of happiness u litarianism will be linked to his ego s cal percep on of human nature while Mill’s drives human ac on. However, one of the fundamental differences between richer and more nuanced ideas will be connected to his concep on of humans as Bentham and Mill’s u litarian moral theories are their concep ons of what human social happiness cons tutes. Bentham proposes a quan ta ve hedonis c interpreta on ‘progressive beings’ and his principle concern with individual while Mill argues that quality of pleasure determines happiness. These differences self-development. 63 64 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sam Allen are important as they determine the ways in which the two thinkers offer individual conduct. Thus, Bentham offers a ‘quan ta ve’ form of hedonism in which contras ng systems for ‘calcula ng’ the value of ac ons and more generally serve to happiness, when reduced to its cons tuents, is determined by the dura on and underpin their moral u litarian theories. intensity of pleasure. This forms his end point for evalua ng the u lity of ac ons.5 Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill Taking an empirical and reduc ve approach, Bentham maintains that happiness Although raised under strict tutelage of his father James Mill and Bentham is con ngent upon pleasurable sensa ons and the absence of pain. In the first himself, J. S. Mill had grown disillusioned with this reduc ve Benthamite hedonism.6 chapter of his Introduc on to the Principles of Morals and Legisla on (1780), Although he had revised much of his hos lity towards Bentham by the me he wrote Bentham states that nature has ‘placed mankind under the governance of two U litarianism in 1861, the work s ll departs significantly from Bentham’s sovereign masters, pain and pleasure’ and that these alone should inform ‘the psychological concep on of happiness. Indeed, Mill offers a more sophis cated standard of right and wrong.’2 Because humans are mo vated by the seeking of account in which the quality of pleasure as opposed to the quan ty is given pleasure and the avoidance of pain this concep on of happiness is, by defini on paramount status. While he agrees that happiness cons tutes ‘pleasure and the hedonis c, and should be valued as the basis of morality. absence of pain,’7 Mill argues that the es ma on of pleasure should not be Moreover, because happiness can be reduced to pleasurable psychological states, Bentham maintains that the quan ty of pleasure determines the value of ac ons. This no on informs his ‘felicific calculus,’ a system which seeks to calculate the value of ac ons according to the pain or pleasure they bring about. Indeed, pleasure is described in units and valued according to intensity, dura on, certainty, propinquity, fecundity, purity and extent (the number of individuals the act affects).3 Taking into account ‘the number of persons whose interests appear to be concerned’ and summing up these pains and pleasures determines the ‘good tendency’ or ‘bad tendency’ of the act.4 It is proposed that this system can be used to calculate the value of any act, be it a piece of governmental legisla on or 65 calculated on “quan ty alone” because some kinds of pleasure ‘are more desirable and more valuable than others.’8 Mill delineates a hierarchy of pleasures in which those that ‘employ the higher facul es,’9 namely one’s intellectual facul es as opposed to more ‘base’ and simple pleasures, are valued higher than ‘sensual indulges’. Mill seems determined to deflect the cri cism levelled at Bentham’s u litarian theory concerning the dehumanizing effect of quan ta ve hedonism; a doctrine ‘worthy of swine.’ Indeed, Mill seeks to describe a happiness that is par cular to humans as progressive beings; ‘a beast’s pleasures do not sa sfy a human being’s concep on of happiness.’10 He famously states that it is be er to ‘be a human being dissa sfied than a pig sa sfied; be er to be Socrates dissa sfied than 66 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sam Allen a fool sa sfied.’11 pleasure and pain. In his 1833 essay Remarks on Bentham’s Philosophy,14 Mill cites Thus for Mill, a balance of lower pleasures such as food and sex, as well as higher pleasures in the form of intellectual or social pursuits, help bring about a state of happiness. Unlike Bentham, Mill does not believe that this state can be measured in the form of pleasurable mental sensa ons.12 Instead, complex mental experiences determine happiness. Furthermore, Mill gives great emphasis to self-development or the cul va on of the mind. Hence, happiness is conceived as an on-going process in which past experiences are built upon. Wendy Donner sums Mill’s ‘theory of life’ succinctly: ‘Out of the building blocks of pleasures are built human happiness and sa sfac on…on this base is erected the edifice of human beings of firm and dis nc ve character that allows humans to pursue meaningful lives.’13 These contras ng theories of happiness ul mately stem from differences between Mill and Bentham’s concep ons of human nature. These different concep ons warrant examina on because they shape each thinker’s applica ons of the ‘greatest happiness principle’ to poli cal ideas of liberty and government. Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill Bentham’s unpublished The Book of Fallacies: ‘[i]n every human breast… self-regarding interest is predominant over social interest; each person’s own individual interest over the interests of all other persons taken together.’15 Hence, Bentham not only sees humans as inherently ego s cal and self-serving, but also incapable of fully comprehending the interests of others. Indeed, he takes a cynical stance on the nature of social rela ons and the existence of social society itself. In The Principles of Morals and Legisla on he argues: ‘the community is a fic ous body’ simply composed of individuals whose personal interests amount to ‘the interest of the community.’16 He further stresses that it is vein to consider the interest of the community ‘without understanding what is the interest of the individual.’17 Predicated on this account of human nature is Bentham’s u litarian role of the legislator. Because the individual is unable to appreciate the interests of the community, and thus can’t promote the greatest happiness principle, Bentham Jeremy Bentham can be seen to subscribe more fully to the doctrine of a ributes this role to the state by regula ng individuals’ behavior. This is achieved psychological egoism than his pupil Mill, in that he saw human mo va on governed primarily through the mechanisms of punishment and reward. In The Principles of by the desire to serve one’s own personal interests. As men oned above, Bentham Morals and Legisla on he states that ‘the business of government is to promote the placed human nature in subjuga on to ‘two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure’ happiness of the society, by punishing and rewarding’18 and this is also echoed in his and thus conceived all human behavior as being determined by the seeking of later work The Leading Principles of a Cons tu onal Code: ‘Whatever is done by pleasure and the avoidance of pain. ‘Interests’ are thus treated within the context of government is done – partly by means of the ma er of punishment, or the fear of it, 67 68 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal partly by means of the ma er of reward, or the hope of it.’19 Thus, Bentham sees the legislator as fashioning the behavior of the ego s cal individual to promote the greatest good of the greatest number through punishment and reward which he directly relates to pleasure and pain. As Frederick Rosen states, Bentham inherited this idea from the French eighteenth–century philosopher Claude Adrien Helve us. An adherent of psychological egoism, Helve us saw the importance of pleasure and pain as tools of legisla on in shaping individual’s behavior to serve the interests of Sam Allen Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill ‘There remained, as a mo ve by which mankind are influenced, and by which they may be guided to their good, only personal interest. Accordingly Bentham’s idea of the world is that of a collec on of persons pursuing each his separate interest or pleasure, and the preven on of whom from jostling one another is unavoidable, may be a empted by hopes and fears derived from three sources – the law, religion, and public opinion.’24 Although Mill later revised these hos li es towards his mentor, U litarianism nevertheless offers a divergent concep on of human nature in which human’s sociability and ‘moral feelings’ are incorporated into the theory of u litarianism. 20 society. Hence Bentham draws on the eighteenth-century poli cal discourse of the power of the legislator in rela on to the self-interested individual to inform his u litarian concep on of law and governance. Indeed, when addressing ‘the ul mate sanc on of the principle of u lity’ in the third chapter of U litarianism, Mill introduces the concept of the ‘moral character’ which can be cul vated by educa on.25 This moral character pertains to ‘a feeling of unity It is this ego s cal concep on of human nature that Mill sets out to with our fellow creatures’ and cons tutes an ‘internal’ sanc on that forms ‘the con- reformulate in U litarianism. Indeed, Mill seeks to realign human nature with the scien ous feelings of mankind.’26 Mill thus seeks to prove that humans are capable u litarian principle of the greatest happiness of the greatest good hence removing of taking into account others interests. He stresses that we all hold a the mechanical purpose of legisla on in fashioning individuals’ behavior. In his 1838 proclivity ‘to be in unity with our fellow creatures’27 and as this grows we begin to essay Bentham, Mill airs his cri cisms of Bentham’s psychological egoism. Indeed he recognize ‘the good of others.’28 Although this sociability needs to be cul vated by states that ‘Bentham’s knowledge of human nature is bounded’21 and that he knew educa on, it is by no means ar ficial and essen ally forms the basis of Mill’s moral ‘li le of human feelings.’22 Most significantly, Mill a acks Bentham’s theory of life in theory. Indeed, Mill asserts that the founda on of the u litarian principle is the which humans are only mo vated by ‘either self-love, love or hatred of others.’23 He ‘social feelings of mankind’ because this internal moral feeling is more binding than elaborates: any external sanc on. This becomes par cularly evident if we consider the poli cal implica ons of 69 Mill’s concep on of human nature and how this shapes his u litarian thought. 70 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal By emphasizing the power of the internal sanc on of moral and social consciousness Mill essen ally inverts Bentham’s u litarian legisla ve system. Bentham asserts that external sanc ons are needed to exert individuals to act in the interests of the community and thus contribute to the general happiness. However, Mill turns this Sam Allen Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill ‘A complete web of corrobora ve associa on is woven round it by the powerful agency of external sanc ons…Every step in poli cal development renders it more so, by removing the sources of opposi on of interest and leveling those inequali es of legal privilege between individuals or classes, owing to which there are large por ons of mankind whose happiness is s ll prac cable to disregard.’31 on its head and suggests that self-developed individuals can act as individual moral This is further stressed in Mill’s more poli cally orientated works On Liberty agents promo ng this end without the need of interference of government. Indeed (1859) and Considera ons of Representa ve Government (1861). In On Liberty, Mill he states: ‘Not only does all strengthening of social es, and all healthy growth of does not propose liberty as an intrinsically valuable state in itself but argues that it society, give to each individual a stronger personal interest in prac cally consul ng serves the purpose of u lity.32 Indeed, Mill asserts that liberty is integral to the the welfare of others, it also leads him to iden fy his feelings more and more with development of individuality and diversity of modes of life in order to promote the their good.’ Thus, Mill seeks to solve one of the theore cal problems Bentham strug- happiness of individuals and society: gled to overcome by proving that the principle of u lity is compa ble with the interests and mo va ons that define human nature. Indeed, Mill’s no on of moral and social sen ment counters those who ques on why they are bound to promote the general happiness in areas where legisla on and public opinion do not interfere. Within this system, individual moral and intellectual self-development are given central importance.29 However, this is not to imply that the legislator does not play a role in Mill’s poli cal u litarian thought. Mill suggests that the role of the legislator is in maintaining condi ons conducive to human self-development and individualism. This is principally achieved by protec ng the rights and liber es of individuals to pursue their own self-development:30 ‘Different persons also require different condi ons for their spiritual development; and can no more exist healthily in the same moral, than all the variety of plants can in the same physical, atmosphere and climate…Such are the differences among human beings in their sources of pleasure, their suscep bili es of pain, and the opera on on them of different physical and moral agencies, that unless there is a corresponding diversity in their modes of life, they neither obtain their fair share of happiness, nor grow up to the mental, moral and aesthe c stature their nature is capable.’33 In Considera ons of Representa ve Government Mill proposes that representa ve forms of government serve two purposes that are related to his u litarian theory. First fully democra c governments with universal suffrage are best suited to iden fying the common good through public delibera on and hence promote the interests of the whole community. Secondly, Mill asserts that poli cal par cipa on also helps further intellectually and morally cul vate individuals who in 71 72 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sam Allen turn help promote the principle of u lity: u litarian theory. While much of his ideas are inversed by Mill and informed by ‘The self-benefi ng quali es are all on the side of the ac ve and energe c character: and the habits and conduct which promote the advantage of each individual member of the community, must be at least a part of those which conduce most in the end to the advancement of the community as a whole.’34 Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill contras ng interpreta ons of human psychology, the founda ons of Bentham’s u litarianism remain the same in Mill’s u lity. Thus, his contribu ons can inform a re-reading of Bentham’s u litarian works. Notes Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill’s differing u litarian theories emanate 1. Wendy Donner, “Mill’s U litarianism” in The Cambridge Companion to Mill, edited by John Skorupski (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 256. 2. Jeremy Bentham, “An introduc on to the principles of morals and legisla on,” in Selected Wri ngs on U litarianism (Ware: Wordsworth Classics, 2000), p. 87. 3. Jeremy Bentham, “An introduc on to the principles of morals and legisla on,” pp. 115118. 4. Ibid., p. 117. concerned with the reforming of the penal code and eighteenth-century 5. Ross Harrison, Bentham (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983), p. 170. cons tu onal discourses, Bentham thus predicates his poli cal u litarian ideas on 6. Wendy Donner, “Mill’s U litarianism”, p. 274. 7. John Stuart Mill, U litarianism (Second Edi on), edited by George Sher (Indianapolis: Hacke Publishing Company, 2001), p. 7. 8. John Stuart Mill, U litarianism, p. 8. 9. Ibid., p. 9. from their contras ng concep ons of human nature. For Bentham, humans are subjected to the psychological states of pleasure and pain. Inherently egois cal beings, we are governed by the need to serve our own interests and this directly corresponds to the a ainment of pleasure and the avoidance of pain. Primarily this reduc ve psychological egoism and postulates that it is the role of the legislator to fashion individuals’ behaviour in line with the principle of u lity. Mill, on the other hand, seeks to prove that the greatest happiness principle corresponds with human nature. If Bentham’s theory is mechanical, Mill’s is organic. Educa on and 10. Ibid., p. 8. 11. Ibid., p. 9. 12. Wendy Donner, “Mill’s U litarianism”, p. 256. self-development play a key role in cul va ng diverse individual moral agents who 13. Ibid., p. 259. promote the principle of u lity rather than violate it. Indeed, Mill’s theory is bound 14. John Stuart Mill, “Remarks on Bentham’s philosophy”, in Collected Works of John Stuart Mill: Volume X, Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), p. 14. to the no on of progress and in this sense is typically nineteenth-century orientated while Bentham offers a more basic, reduc ve and sta c framework. Despite these significant differences, Mill’s refinements of Bentham’s theory are just that; 15. Jeremy Bentham, The Book of Fallacies (London: Hunt, 1824), pp. 392-393. 16. Ibid., p. 88. 17. Ibid., p. 89. 18. Ibid., p. 154. refinements seeking to illuminate, develop and ul mately defend Bentham’s 73 74 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Sam Allen Bibliography Notes 19. Jeremy Bentham, “Leading Principles of a Cons tu onal Code,” in Selected Wri ngs on U litarianism (Ware: Wordsworth Classics, 2000), p. 471. 20. Frederick Rosen, Classical U litarianism, p. 93 21. John Stuart Mill, “Bentham,” in Mill on Bentham and Coleridge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), p. 62. 22. John Stuart Mill, “Bentham,” p. 63. 23. Ibid., p. 66. 24. Ibid., p. 70. 25. John Stuart Mill, U litarianism, p. 27. 26. Ibid., p. 29. 27. Ibid., p. 32. 28. John Stuart Mill, U litarianism, p. 32 29. Wendy Donner, “Mill’s U litarianism”, p. 272. 30. Ibid., p. 278. 31. John Stuart Mill, U litarianism, p. 33. 32. Ross Harrison, “John Stuart Mill, mid-Victorian” in Gareth Stedman Jones & Gregory Claeys, eds., The Cambridge History of Nineteenth-Century Poli cal Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), p. 307. 33. 34. Comparison of the u litarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill Secondary Literature Donner, Wendy, “Mill’s U litarianism” in The Cambridge Companion to Mill, edited by John Skorupski (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 255-292. Mill, John Stuart, “On Liberty” in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks, 2008), pp. 201-467. Mill, John Stuart, “Remarks on Bentham’s philosophy”, in Collected Works of John Stuart Mill: Volume X, Essays on Ethics, Religion and Society (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969). Mill, John Stuart, U litarianism (Second Edi on), edited by George Sher (Indianapolis: Hacke Publishing Company, 2001). Primary Works Bentham, Jeremy, “An introduc on to the principles of morals and legisla on,” in Selected Wri ngs on U litarianism (Ware: Wordsworth Classics, 2000), pp. 75-309. Bentham, Jeremy, “Leading Principles of a Cons tu onal Code,” in Selected Wri ngs on U litarianism (Ware: Wordsworth Classics, 2000), pp. 463-475. John Stuart Mill, “On Liberty” in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks, 2008), p. 75. Bentham, Jeremy, The Book of Fallacies (London: Hunt, 1824). Mill, John Stuart, “Bentham,” in Mill on Bentham and Coleridge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978). Mill, John Stuart, “Considera ons on Representa ve Government” in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks, 2008). Mill, John Stuart, “Considera ons on Representa ve Government” in On Liberty and Other Essays (Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks, 2008), p. 249. Bibliography Secondary Literature Harrison, Ross, Bentham (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983). Harrison, Ross, “John Stuart Mill, mid-Victorian” in eds. Gareth Stedman Jones & Gregory Claeys, The Cambridge History of Nineteenth-Century Poli cal Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), pp. 295-318. Rosen, Frederick, Classical U litarianism from Hume to Mill (London: Routledge, 2003). 75 76 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair ignited a poli cal scandal and Reagan was under pressure to address the Assess the significance of the Iran-contra affair. Harry Sophocleous issue. On November 13th the President announced that the total deliveries could easily fit into a single cargo plane, a fabrica on considering, by this point, at least 2000 missiles had already been delivered. Furthermore, Reagan declared that there ‘[The President] shall care that the laws be faithfully exercised.’ (Ar cle 2, Sec on 3 of the United States of America Cons tu on).1 was no third country involved. Twelve days later, the chickens had come home to roost, and on November 25, Reagan and his A orney General Edwin Meese had admi ed to the redirec on of funds, and NSC director Admiral John Poindexter had On August 12, 1987, the for eth president of the United States, Ronald resigned whilst Marine Lieutenant Colonel Oliver North had been relieved of his Reagan, addressed the na on from the Oval Office. He sat behind his desk, du es.3 sheepishly staring into the eyes of every American watching, and acknowledged that he had lost sight of the Founding Fathers’ vision when he declared: ‘I was stubborn in my pursuit of a policy that went astray”.2 When Deputy A orney General Lawrence Walsh was asked how he thinks Iran-contra will be remembered in history, his answer was clear: “I think it’ll be remembered as a non-sordid disregard of cons tu onal restraints. I think the This policy was the Iran-contra affair. In essence, America contravened the president was wrong, he was defiant, he was deliberate, but he wasn’t dirty”.4 His trade embargo on Iran by selling arms and direc ng the funds to rebels in Nicaragua predic on was right. Memory of the scandal appears to have fractured into two despite numerous Boland Amendments prohibi ng such aid. A series of events that conven onal strands: the first draws upon the inves ga onal conclusions that focus necessitated this admi ance had begun to snowball when a cargo plane ferrying on the individual shortcomings of Reagan and his aides; the second views the scandal American aid was shot down over Nicaragua on October 5, 1986. The only survivor as a failure in the American system of poli cs. Undoubtedly, both arguments possess from the plane crash was captured with secret documents leading back to the great validity when discussing the implica ons of the Iran-contra affair, which this Na onal Security Council (NSC). Suspicions were beginning to arise when a Lebanese essay will analyze and expand upon. However, the issue possesses greater magazine Al Shiraa published a story that NSC director Robert McFarlane had visited complexi es. In order to understand the true significance of the Iran-contra scandal, Teheran on a secret mission. Ali Akbar Hashemi, the speaker of the Iranian one must leave the shores of the United States and look at the affair through the parliament, then confirmed this the following day. These bombshell disclosures 77 78 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair prism of interna onal rela ons. Here, one is able to see its subsequent scandalous episode, The Tower Commission offered its moderate sugges ons to impact on the nature of Western nego a on with terrorist forces, as well as the achieve future preven on, one of which recommended that ‘Congress consider exposure of the United States as an imperialist force that was willing to undermine replacing the exis ng intelligence commi ees”.8 Such conclusions powerfully shaped the system of democracy to extend its influence in the Middle East. However, the public percep on of the crisis as an innocuous failure of management. The Iran-contra affair has been le unresolved and relegated to the mere footnote of recommenda ons were not headline grabbing or likely to a ract any interest from Reagan’s presidency - this essay will a empt to highlight its relevance. the United States media, thus ensuring that the scandal became a distant memory. When the scandal came to light on November 25, 1985, the world’s media exploded and the affair stole the front pages of every major newspaper across the One magazine noted that ‘a er a day of obligatory headlines, news of the report vanished as abruptly as an April snowfall’.9 globe. The New York Times printed a par cularly interes ng headline the following The limited poli cal ramifica ons were reinforced when all of Walsh’s eleven day that read: ‘The Iran Affair: A Presidency Damaged’.5 However, why was Reagan’s convic ons were pardoned in June 1992.10 Instead, the only tangible poli cal presidency merely ‘damaged’ and not under threat? It is this knee-jerk reac on consequences that illustrated any significance was the ini al impulse for Poindexter from the media that is sustained throughout history as a result of the limited to resign and North to be relieved of his du es. Reagan’s admi ance that ‘you take poli cal implica ons of the Iran-contra affair. your knocks, you learn your lessons, and then you move on’ suggests that this was Unlike the Watergate scandal, which forced Richard Nixon’s resigna on in 1974, the Iran-contra affair did li le to weaken the Reagan administra on. Despite the President’s approval ra ng ini ally dropping from 67% to 46%, levels quickly returned to above 50% only a year and a half later.6 American historian Phillip Jenkins offers the explana on for this poli cal stability by arguing that ‘the public does not become angry enough to support a president’s removal while the merely deemed an unpopular policy solvable by an administra ve reshuffle.11 The public were mere spectators to a succession of sensa onalist headlines and televised hearings that would ul mately degenerate into an elaborate public rela ons exercise in damage control.12 The underplaying of the scandal’s significance through the sta c nature of poli cal personnel, despite events, has led poli cal scien sts, such as Adam 7 economy is booming’. However, this fails to recognize the influence of the various inves ga onal commi ees in shaping public opinion. A er months of studying the 79 Wildavsky, to approve of the Iran-contra affair ‘fading into insignificance’.13 However, deeming the affair as an aberra onal lapse by an 80 deserved Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous ina en ve president to control his aides, leaves analysis of the scandal limited in were framed in the eighteenth century. As a result, there have been calls to learn depth, and fails to address the systema c irregulari es that were manifest during the from the episode. Historian Arthur Schlesinger has deemed the American affair. cons tu on outdated and calls for a move towards a parliamentary system.17 Given The scandal was not the secret delivery of arms, or even the lying and hypocrisy that accompanied it. Instead, the real scandal lay in the subversion of law, congressional authority, and the will of the public in order to produce immoral and counterproduc ve policies. Furthermore, the Iran-contra affair was no aberra on. Instead, it was the product of a long process of presiden al aggrandizement, congressional fickleness, and judicial connivance.14 Woodrow Wilson recognized ‘the ini a ve in foreign affairs, in which the President posses without any restric on The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair the decentralized nature of American poli cs such reforms are unrealis c. Instead, presidents should be forced to acknowledge the risks associated with exercising the power and preroga ve of government by the enforcement of stricter due diligence when it comes to foreign policy. Indeed, the Iran-contra affair ar culated the disadvantages of arbitrary power and should have triggered a process that saw Congress grow in influence on interna onal ma ers. Alas, this was not the case. Vital lessons were not learnt, and history was le whatever, is virtually the power to control them absolutely’.15 Moreover, in the 1936 to repeat itself. Echoes of the Iran-contra affair can be found in the case, U.S. v. Cur ss-Wright Export Corpora on, Jus ce George Sutherland held that Bush-administra on and the decision in early 2007 to reconfigure policy in the ‘the president [operates] as the sole organ of the federal government in the field of Middle East. In order to prac ce outside of the Congressional appropria ons interna onal rela ons’ and that ‘within the interna onal field [Congress] must o en process, covert opera ons were implemented. In the a empt to keep the Lebanese accord to the president a degree of discre on and freedom from statuary Prime Minister, Fouad Siniora, in power against a persistent opposi on led by restric on which would not be admissible were domes c affairs alone involved’.16 Hezbollah, clandes ne support was given to the Siniora government. Por ons of this The Iran-contra affair exposed the weakness of Congress vis-à-vis the presiden al aid found its way into the hands of emerging Sunni radical groups with ideological execu ve branch in the sphere of foreign policy. This hegemonic environment es to Al Qaeda.18 Iran-contra was the moment in history when America decided encouraged the president’s agents to pursue a policy that risked execu ve that no authorita ve figure would ask serious ques ons of the hegemonic overshoot. By circumven ng, and repeatedly lying to Congress, the scandal presiden al system. The cons tu on has morphed into a manipula ve puppet threatened to undermine the cons tu onal ideals of interna onal rela ons that show, which has le a na on in a constant brace posi on fearing inevitable 81 82 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal presiden al overreach in foreign policy. Harry Sophocleous The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair Margaret Thatcher is one leader who may have asked such ques ons. Like The Iran-contra affair undermined Reagan and his administra on on one of the strongest, and most supported principles that they proudly proclaimed; non-nego a on with terrorists. On November 11, 1986, eight days following the leak by the Lebanese government, The New York Times raised ques ons over the revela on of the arms-for-hostages deal and the implica ons for ‘America’s credibility abroad’.19 Such inquiries were right to be made. On April 15, 1986, Reagan had promised that there would be no ‘appeasement of evil… no sanctuary for terror. Terrorism undeterred will deflect the winds of freedom’.20 The Iran-contra affair however, exposed such asser ons as empty rhetoric. Indeed, former Iranian President, Abolhassan Banisadr, told a Lebanese newspaper that Americans ‘are capable of making 180-degress turns in their policy’.21 Reagan, the Bri sh Prime Minister had been insistent that one must never nego ate with terrorists. However, when repeatedly ques oned on the affair, she held a consistently conserva ve approach. At one point she stated: ‘One simply has to recognize that you can’t carry on the business of government unless some things are confiden al… We are dealing with leaders who understand the big issues and who are not going to be sidetracked from the big issues’.23 This muted response was not merely an a empt to maintain the special rela onship between Britain and the United States.24 Thatcher was hesitant in condemning America’s ac ons because she was planning clandes ne opera ons in Ireland. No ac on had been taken when it was contemplated that the Bri sh withdraw from Northern Ireland in 1981.25 However, in 1990, three years following the sales-of-arms deal was made public, Thatcher authorized her Secretary of State Peter Brooke to hold secret talks with IRA The affair did not just act as a signal to its adversaries that hostage taking was leadership.26 This shi from hesita on to authoriza on can be in part a ributed to a useful instrument in extrac ng poli cal and financial concessions from the West, the Iran-contra affair in that it established a precedent for Western powers to but also undermined any credibility of U.S. cri cism of other states’ devia on from nego ate with terrorists and such nego a ons remain in prac ce today. On April 20, the principles of non-nego a on and no concessions to terrorists.22 It is this la er 2014, four French journalists were mysteriously released a er ten months in Syria, point that would illustrate best the impact that Iran-contra had on the interna onal sparking ransom rumors. Al-Qaeda had received £75 million from ransoms since stage. Following the outbreak of the scandal, Western powers must have asked 2008.27 themselves, ‘If America can do it, then why can’t we?’ A er all, America was the leading power in the Western world. Furthermore, the Iran-contra affair exposed America to be an imperialist power seeking to extend its influence across the globe. This was vociferously 83 84 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous ar culated in the Middle East. Indeed, the media characterized the United States as As a result, this triggered interna onal implica ons that are s ll being felt in current an interna onal bully: ‘The bourgeois democracy is nothing but a cover behind which global poli cs. Indeed, when the two planes flew into New York’s World Trade Centre the imperialist class hides to carry out arbitrary opera ons and brutality both in on September 11, 2001, Saddam Hussein approved by asser ng that the a ack domes c and foreign policy’.28 A Turkish report asserted that ‘all [Reagan’s] reali es happened on a na on that ‘exports evil, in terms of corrup on and criminality, not are based on the globalist doctrines of the greatest imperial states’ ruling circles who only to any place to which its armies travel but also to any place where its movies consider all other countries and peoples pawns in their hegemonis c policies’.29 go’.32 It cannot be doubted that the actor-turned-president, Reagan, had a domino to Middle Eastern na ons felt America’s ambi ons were to gain control of the play in the deteriora on towards a war on terror that the world finds itself Organiza on of the Petroleum Expor ng Countries (OPEC), establish a Westernized engulfed in today. regime, and manipulate the terrorist groups.30 Iran-contra illustrated to the Islamic The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair Notes regions of the Middle East that the United States was unable to accept their 1. The Cons tu on of the United States, h p://www.franklincountypa.gov/da/ Documents/US%20Cons tu on.pdf [Accessed 1st December 2014]. civiliza on as unique and cooperate by maintaining the mul -civiliza onal character 2. R. Reagan, ‘Address to the Na on on the Iran Arms and Contra Aid Controversy and Administra on Goals’, August 12, 1987, h p://www.reagan.utexas.edu/archives/ speeches/1987/081287d.htm , [Accessed 1st December 2014]. 3. J. Mitchell, Execu ve Privilege: Two Centuries of White House Scandals (New York: Hippocrene Books, 1992), pp. 358-91. 4. B. Woodward, Shadow: Five Presidents and the Legacy of Watergate (London: Simon & Schuster, 1999), p. 179. 5. ‘The Iran Affair: A Presidency Damaged’, The New York Times, November 26 1985. 6. J. Pa erson, The Restless Giant: The United States from Watergate to Bush v. Gore (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), pp. 207-13. 7. P. Jenkins, Decade of Nightmares: The End of the Six es and the Marking of the Eigh es America (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 234-5. 8. Tower, J., Snowcro , B., and Muskie, E., ‘The Iran-Contra Affair’, in P. Hays, Brenda Vallance, and A. van Tassel, America Defense Policy, vol.7 (Bal more: The John Hopkins University Press, 1997), p.203. 9. R. Williams, Poli cal Scandals in the USA (London: Routledge, 1998), p. 50. 10. Pa erson, Restless Giant, p.213. 11. R. Reagan, ‘Address to the Na on on Iran-Contra’, March 4 1987, h p:// millercenter.org/president/speeches/speech-3414, [Accessed 2nd December 2014]. of global poli cs. Hence the affair undoubtedly contributed to the an -Americanism that was beginning to fester on the con nent. In his famous review of the Roman Empire, Edward Gibbon stated that: ‘History… is li le more than the register of crimes, follies, and misfortunes of 31 mankind’. This defini on offers some explana on as why the Iran-contra affair fails to get men oned in any discussion regarding the Reagan presidency or American poli cal history. With an emphasis being placed on the lack of physical results from the scandal by the journalis c dominance in the historiography, it is no surprise that the general conclusion deems the affair insignificant. However, the Iran-contra affair exposed gaping cons tu onal and congressional holes that were unaddressed. 85 86 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Harry Sophocleous Notes 12. J. Marshall, P. Sco , and J. Hunter, The Iran-Contra Connec on (Boston: South End Press, 1987), p. 230. 13. A. Wildavsky, The Beleaguered Presidency (New Brunswick: Transac on Publishers, 1991), p. 238. 14. T. Draper, A Very Thin Line: The Iran-Contra Affair (New York: Hill and Wang, 1991), p. 582. 15. J. Lindsay, Congress and the Poli cs of U.S. Foreign Policy (Bal more: The John Hopkins University Press, 1994), pp. 141-4. The significance of the Iran-Contra Affair Notes 32. P. Clawson and B. Rubin, ‘An -Americanism: in the Middle East’, in P. Hollander, Understanding An -Americanism: Its Origins and Impact at Home and Abroad (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 2004), pp. 124-5. Bibliography Secondary literature Bovard, J., Terrorism and Tyranny: Trampling Freedom, Jus ce, and Peace to Rid the World of Evil (Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003). 16. Ibid. 17. A. Schlesinger, The Imperial Presidency (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1989), pp. 461-3. Chavira, D., ‘Evidence and Analysis: The Iran-Contra Affair as Seen Through American, Middle Eastern, and Soviet News Sources’, University of Pennsylvania CUREJ (January 2014). 18. S. Hersh, ‘The Redirec on: Is the Administra on’s new policy benefi ng our enemies on the war on terrorism?’, The New Yorker, March 5 2007, h p:// www.newyorker.com/magazine/2007/03/05/the-redirec on , [Accessed 27th November 2014]. Clawson, P. and Rubin, B., ‘An -Americanism: in the Middle East’, in P. Hollander, Understanding An -Americanism: Its Origins and Impact at Home and Abroad (Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 2004). 19. ‘U.S. Policy on Terror’, The New York Times, November 11, 1986. Draper, T., A Very Thin Line: The Iran-Contra Affair (New York: Hill and Wang, 1991). 20. J. Bovard, Terrorism and Tyranny: Trampling Freedom, Jus ce, and Peace to Rid the World of Evil (Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), p. 26. 21. D. Chavira, ‘Evidence and Analysis: The Iran-Contra Affair as Seen Through American, Middle Eastern, and Soviet News Sources’, University of Pennsylvania CUREJ (January 2014). 22. M. Ranstorp, Hizb’allah in Lebanon: The Poli cs of the Western Hostage Crisis (New York: St Mar ns Press, 1997), p. 203. Freedman, R., The Middle East from the Iran-Contra Affair to the In fada (New York: Syracuse University Press, 1991). Gibbon, E., The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (London: Joseph Ogle Robinson, 1830). Jenkins, P., Decade of Nightmares: The End of the Six es and the Marking of the Eigh es America (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006). 23. G. Smith, Reagan and Thatcher (London: Bodley Head, 1990), pp. 204-13. 24. Ibid. 25. O. Bowco , ‘Thatcher cabinet “wobbled” over IRA hunger strikers’, The Guardian, December 30 2011. 26. N. Wa , ‘Thatcher gave approval to talks with IRA’, The Guardian, October 16 1999. Lindsay, J., Congress and the Poli cs of U.S. Foreign Policy (Bal more: The John Hopkins University Press, 1994). 27. J. Lichfield, ‘Ransom rumours a er French Syrian hostages go free’, The Independent, April 20 2014. And, D. Blair, ‘Should government spay a ransom for hostages?’, The Telegraph, August 21 2014. Lynch M., and Bogen, D., The Spectacle of History: Speech, Text, and Memory at the Iran-Contra Hearings (Durham: Duke University Press, 1996). 28. Chivara, ‘Evidence and Analysis’. 29. Ibid. 30. Ibid. 31. E. Gibbon, The History of the Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (London: Joseph Ogle Robinson, 1830), p. 31. Islam, I., ‘An -Americanism in the Muslim World’, in B. O’Connor and M. Griffiths, The Rise of An -Americanism (London: Routledge, 2006). Marshall, J., Sco , P., and Hunter, J., The Iran-Contra Connec on (Boston: South End Press, 1987). 87 Mitchell, J., Execu ve Privilege: Two Centuries of White House Scandals (New York: Hippocrence Books, 1992). Pa erson, J., The Restless Giant: The United States from Watergate to Bush v. Gore (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). 88 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Winter Issue Bibliography Secondary literature Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Committee 2014/15 Ranstorp, M., Hizb’allah in Lebanon: The Poli cs of the Western Hostage Crisis (New York: St Mar ns Press, 1997). Schlesinger, A., The Imperial Presidency (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1989). Editor in Chief Smith, G., Reagan and Thatcher (London: Bodley Head, 1990). Tower, J., Snowcro , B., and Muskie, E., ‘The Iran-Contra Affair’, in P. Hays, Brenda Vallance, and A. van Tassel, America Defense Policy, vol.7 (Bal more: The John Hopkins University Press, 1997). Wildavsky, A., The Beleaguered Presidency (New Brunswick: Transac on Publishers, 1991). Shabbir Bokhari Commissioning Editor Sub Editor Catriona Tassell Becky Adkins Williams, R., Poli cal Scandals in the USA (London: Routledge, 1998). Head of Design Woodward, B., Shadow: Five Presidents and the Legacy of Watergate (London: Simon & Schuster, 1999). H. Zinn, A People’s History of the United States: From 1492 to the Present (New York: Longman, 1996). Primary literature Blair, D., ‘Should government spay a ransom for hostages?’, The Telegraph, August 21 2014. Bowco , O., ‘Thatcher cabinet “wobbled” over IRA hunger strikers’, The Guardian, December 30 2011. The Cons tu on of the United States Sandip Kana Design Editors Social Team Phoebe Cousins Jacob Kishere Nirah Knight Lauren Macaskill Charlie Roden Jonathan Sayegh Essay Editors h p://www.franklincountypa.gov/da/Documents/US%20Cons tu on.pdf [Accessed 1st December 2014]. Sam Allen, Mamataj Begum, Lisa Bull, Pearce Branigan, David Clements , Hersh ,S., ‘The Redirec on: Is the Administra on’s new policy benefi ng our enemies on the war on terrorism?’, The New Yorker, March 5 2007 Rhiannon Doran, Kieran Jones, Carl Lentz, Sebas an Lowe, Anna Macaninch, h p://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2007/03/05/the-redirec on [Accessed 27th November 2014]. Lauren Macaskill, Vivan Nabukenya, Amy Sinclair, ‘The Iran Affair: A Presidency Damaged’, The New York Times, November 26 1985. Jake Stephen Vo, and Poppy Waring 89 90 Queen Mary History Undergraduate Journal Contributors Sam Allen Sebas an Lowe Bethany Price Harry Sophocleous László Zorya Like the History Journal on /QueenMaryHistoryJournal Follow the History Journal on @QMHUJ Copyright of images used on the cover and back with permission from, Queen Mary University of London Archives. 92
© Copyright 2024