A l l T h e y K n o w : A S t u d y i n M u l t i - A g e n t A u t o e p i s t e m i c Reasoning PRELIMINARY REPORT Gerhard Lakemeyer Institute of Computer Science I I I University of Bonn Romerstr. 164 5300 Bonn 1, Germany gerhard@cs.uni-bonn.de Abstract W i t h few exceptions the s t u d y o f n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning has been confined to the single-agent case. However, it has been recognized t h a t intelligent agents often need to reason a b o u t other agents and their a b i l i t y to reason n o n m o n o t o n i c a l l y . In this paper we present a form a l i z a t i o n of m u l t i - a g e n t autoepistemic reasoning, w h i c h n a t u r a l l y extends earlier work by Levesque. In p a r t i c u l a r , we propose an n-agent m o d a l belief logic, which allows us to express t h a t a f o r m u l a (or f i n i t e set of t h e m ) is all an agent knows, w h i c h m a y include beliefs a b o u t w h a t other agents believe. T h e paper presents a f o r m a l semantics of the logic in the possibleworld framework. We provide an axiomatizat i o n , w h i c h is complete for a large f r a g m e n t of the logic and sufficient to characterize interesti n g f o r m s of m u l t i - a g e n t autoepistemic reasoni n g . We also extend the stable set and stable expansion ideas of single-agent autoepistemic logic to the m u l t i - a g e n t case. 1 Introduction W h i l e the s t u d y o f n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning f o r m a l i s m s has been at the forefront of f o u n d a t i o n a l research in knowledge representation for q u i t e some t i m e , work in this area has concentrated on the single-agent case w i t h only few exceptions. T h i s focus on single agents is somewhat surprisi n g , since there is l i t t l e d o u b t t h a t agents, w h o have been invested w i t h n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning mechanisms, should be able to reason a b o u t other agents and their a b i l i t y to reason n o n m o n o t o n i c a l l y as well. For e x a m ple, if we assume the c o m m o n default t h a t birds norm a l l y fly a n d if J i l l tells Jack t h a t she has j u s t b o u g h t a b i r d , then J i l l s h o u l d be able to infer t h a t Jack t h i n k s t h a t her b i r d flies. M u l t i - a g e n t n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning is also crucial when agents need to coordinate their act i v i t y . P'or e x a m p l e , assume I promised a f r i e n d ( w h o is always on t i m e ) to meet h i m at a restaurant at 7 P M . If I leave my house k n o w i n g t h a t I w i l l not m a k e it there by 7 P M , 1 w i l l p r o b a b l y n o t change my plans and s t i l l go to the restaurant. A f t e r a l l , I know t h a t my friend has 376 Distributed Al no reason to believe t h a t I am n o t on my way to meet h i m and t h a t he w i l l therefore w a i t for m e . N o t e t h a t I reason a b o u t m y friends default a s s u m p t i o n t o w a i t i n this case. O t h e r examples f r o m areas like p l a n n i n g and t e m p o r a l p r o j e c t i o n can be f o u n d in [ M o r 9 0 ] . One of the m a i n f o r m a l i s m s of n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoni n g is autoepistemic logic (e.g. [ M o o 8 5 ] ) . T h e basic idea is t h a t the beliefs of agents are closed under perfect introspection, t h a t is, they k n o w 1 w h a t they know and do n o t k n o w . N o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning comes a b o u t in this f r a m e w o r k in t h a t agents can draw inferences on the basis of their o w n ignorance. T h e f o l l o w i n g e x a m ple by M o o r e illustrates this feature: I can reasonably conclude t h a t I have no older b r o t h e r s i m p l y because I do n o t know of any older b r o t h e r of m i n e . A particular f o r m a l i z a t i o n of a u t o e p i s t e m i c reasoning is due to Levesque [Lev90], w h o proposes a logic of only-knowing {OL), w h i c h is a classical m o d a l logic extended by a new m o d a l i t y to express t h a t a f o r m u l a is all an agent believes. An advantage of t h i s approach is t h a t , rather t h a n h a v i n g to appeal to n o n - s t a n d a r d inference rules as in Moore's o r i g i n a l f o r m u l a t i o n , OL captures autoepistemic reasoning using o n l y the classical n o t i o n s of logical consequence and t h e o r e m h o o d . In t h i s paper, we propose a p r o p o s i t i o n a l m u l t i - a g e n t extension of OL. We p r o v i d e a f o r m a l semantics w i t h i n the possible-world f r a m e w o r k and a p r o o f theory, which is complete for a large f r a g m e n t of the logic. T h e new logic also leads us to n a t u r a l extensions of notions like stable sets and stable expansions, w h i c h were o r i g i n a l l y developed for the single-agent case. General m u l t i - a g e n t n o n m o n o t o n i c reasoning form a l i s m s have received very l i t t l e a t t e n t i o n u n t i l recently. 2 A n o t a b l e exception is work by M o r g e n stern and G u e r r e i r o [ M o r 9 0 , M G 9 2 ] , w h o consider b o t h m u l t i - a g e n t a u t o e p i s t e m i c reasoning a n d m u l t i - a g e n t circ u m s c r i p t i o n theories. On the a u t o e p i s t e m i c side, they propose m u l t i - a g e n t versions of stable sets, w h i c h a l 1 While we are concerned w i t h belief and, in particular, allow agents to have false beliefs, we nevertheless use the terms knowledge and belief interchangeably. 2 There has also been work applying nonmonotonic theories to special multi-agent settings such as speech acts (e.g. [Per87, AK88]). Unlike our work, these approaches are not concerned with general purpose multi-agent nonmonotonic reasoning. low agents to reason about other agents' nonmonotonic inferences. In contrast to our work, however, these stable sets are not justified by an independent semantic account. Recently, and independently of our work, Halpern [Hal93] also extended Levesque's logic OL to the multi-agent case. While Halpern's logic and ours share many (but not all) properties, the respective model theories are quite different. In particular, while our approach remains within classical possible-world semantics, Halpern uses concepts very much related to the so-called knowledge structures of [FHV91]. Using the same technique, Halpern also extends the notion of only-knowing proposed in [HM84] to the multi-agent case. There, however, agents are not capable of reasoning about other agent's nonmonotonic inferences because only-knowing is used only as a meta-logical concept. The rest of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 defines the logic OLn, extending Levesque's logic of onlyknowing to many agents. Besides a formal semantics we also provide a proof theory, which is complete for a large fragment of 0Ln. Furthermore, we look at the properties of formulas in 0Ln which uniquely determine the beliefs of an agent and are thus of particular interest to knowledge representation. Section 3 considers examples of multi-agent autoepistemic reasoning as modeled by 0Ln Section 4 shows how 0Ln yields natural multiagent versions of stable sets and stable expansions. Finally, we summarize the results of the paper and point to some future work in Section 5. 2 T h e Logic 0Ln After introducing the syntax of the logic, we define the semantics in two stages. First we describe that part of the semantics that does not deal with only-knowing. In fact, this is just an ordinary possible-world semantics for n agents with perfect introspection. Then we introduce the necessary extensions that give us the semantics of only-knowing. Finally, we present a proof theoretic account, which is complete for a large fragment of the logic, and discuss properties of the logic which are important in the context of knowledge representation. Lakemeyer 377 of a world w, which corresponds intuitively to the real world, and a set of worlds W', which determine the beliefs of the agent. There is no need for an explicit accessibility relation, since the worlds in M are globally accessible from every world and a sentence is believed just in case it is true at all worlds in W. Unfortunately, such a simple model does not extend to the multi-agent case and we are forced to a more complicated semantics with explicit accessibility relations as defined above.7 For this reason, the extension of Levesque's logic OL to many agents turns out to be a non-trivial exercise. 2.3 The Canonical M o d e l It is well known that, as far as basic formulas are concerned, it suffices to look at just one, the so-called canonical model [HC84, HM92]. This canonical model will be used later on to define the semantics of only-knowing. The central idea behind canonical models are maximally consistent sets. D e f i n i t i o n 6 Maximally consistent sets Given any proof theory of K45n and the usual notion of theoremhood and consistency, a set of basic formulas T is called m a x i m a l l y c o n s i s t e n t iff T is consistent and f o r every basic either is contained in T. The canonical K45n-model Mc has as worlds precisely all the maximally consistent sets and a world w' is i n accessible from w just in case all of i's beliefs at w are included in w'. D e f i n i t i o n 7 The Canonical K45n-Model Mc The canonical model Mc = (Wc, Tl, R 1 , . . . , Rn) is a Kripke structure such that The following (well known) theorem tells us that nothing is lost from a logical point of view if we confine our attention to the canonical model. T h e o r e m 1 Mc is a model and for every set of basic formulas T, T is satisfiable iff it is satisfiable in Mc. 2.4 T h e Semantics of A l l T h e y K n o w Given this classical possible-world framework, what does it mean for an agent i to only-know, say, an atom p at some world w in a model Ml Certainly, i should believe p, that is, all worlds that are i-accessible from w should make p true. Furthermore, i should believe as little else as possible apart from p. For example, i should neither believe q nor believe that j believes p etc. Minimizing knowledge using possible worlds simply means maximizing the number of accessible worlds. Thus, in our example, there should be an accessible world where q is false and another one where j does not believe p and so on. It should be clear that in order for w to satisfy 7In essence, if we have more than 1 agent and a global set of worlds for each agent, the agents would be mutually introspective, which is not what we want. 378 Distributed Al Lakemeyer 379 What are examples of determinate formulas? In the single-agent case, it has been shown that all objective formulas (no modalities at all) are determinate. Not surprisingly, objective formulas are also i-determinate. In fact, this result can be generalized to include all basic i-objective formulas. Theorem 6 All basic i-objective formulas are i-determinate. Other examples of i-determinate formulas, which are not i-objective, include which allow agents to reason nonmonotonically and are discussed in more detail in Section 3. So far we have only considered basic i-determinate sentences. Does the above result extend to non-basic i-objective formulas as well? The answer, surprisingly, is: sometimes but not always! For example, it is not hard to show that the formula (where p is an atom) is also i-determinate, that is, the beliefs of agent i are uniquely determined if all i knows is that all j knows is p. However, the formula is not i-determinate because In other words, it is impossible for i to only-know that j does not only-know p. Intuitively, for i to know that j does not only-know p, i needs to have some evidence in terms of a basic belief or non-belief of j. It is because of properties like that our axiomatization is not complete for all of 3 Multi-agent Nonmonotonic Reasoning While our axiomatization is complete only for a subset of 0 L n , it is nevertheless strong enough to model interesting cases of multi-agent nonmonotonic reasoning. Here are two examples: 1. Let p be agent i's secret and suppose i makes the following assumption: unless 1 know that j knows my secret assume that j does not know it. We can prove in 0Ln that if this assumption is all i believes then he indeed believes that j does not know his secret. Formally A formal derivation of this theorem of 0Ln can be obtained as follows. Let . The justifications in the following derivation indicate which axioms or previous derivations have been used to derive the current line. PL or indicate that reasoning in either standard propositional logic or is used is without further analysis. To see that i's beliefs may evolve nonmonotonically given 12 In contrast, is satisfiable in Halpern's logic. Note that if we replace we obtain regular singleagent autoepistemic reasoning. 13 380 Distributed Al References 5 Conclusion We proposed a multi-agent logic of only-knowing that extends earlier work by Levesque regarding the singleagent case. Our logic gives a semantic and proof theoretic account of autoepistemic reasoning for many knowers. Notions like stable set and stable expansion fall out as natural extensions of single-agent autoepistemic logic. As for future work, it would be interesting to obtain a complete axiomatization for all of OL. Also, as noted earlier, there are subtle differences between 0 L n and Halpern's logic. Halpern showed that every valid sentence in his logic is also valid in 0 L n and that the valid sentences of both logics coincide when restricted to However, there are sentences such as that are valid in 0 L n but not in Halpern's case. For a better comparison of the two approaches it would be interesting to see which modifications are necessary to obtain identical logics. Finally, a more expressive firstorder language should be considered to make 0 L n more applicable in real world domains. We conjecture that an approach as in [Lev90] could be adapted for this purpose without great difficulty. [ A K 8 8 ] A p p e l t , D. and K o n o l i g e , K., A P r a c t i c a l N o n m o n o t o n i c T h e o r y of Reasoning a b o u t Speech A c t s , i n Proc. o f the 26th C o n f o f the A C L , 1988. [ F H V 9 1 ] A M o d e l - T h e o r e t i c A n a l y s i s of Knowledge, J o u r n a l o f the A C M 9 1 ( 2 ) , 1991, p p . 3 8 2 - 4 2 8 . [Hal93] H a l p e r n , J . Y . , Reasoning a b o u t o n l y knowi n g w i t h m a n y agents, in Proc. of the 11th N a t i o n a l Conference on A r t i f i c i a l Intelligence (AAAI-93). [ H M 8 4 ] H a l p e r n , J . Y . and Moses, Y . O., Towards a T h e o r y of K n o w l e d g e a n d Ignorance: Prel i m i n a r y R e p o r t , i n Proceedings o f T h e N o n M o n o t o n i c W o r k s h o p , New P a l t z , N Y , 1984, pp.125-143. [ H M 9 2 ] H a l p e r n , J . Y . and Moses, Y . O., A G u i d e t o Completeness a n d C o m p l e x i t y for M o d a l Logics of Knowledge and Belief, A r t i f i c i a l Intelligence 5 4 , 1992, p p . 3 1 9 - 3 7 9 . [HC84] Hughes, G. E. and Cresswell, M. J . , A Compani o n to M o d a l Logic, M e t h u e n & C o . , L o n d o n , 1984. [Hin62] H i n t i k k a , J . , Knowledge and Belief: A n I n t r o duction to the Logic of the Two N o t i o n s , Cornell U n i v e r s i t y Press, 1962. [Hin71] H i n t i k k a , J . , Semantics for P r o p o s i t i o n a l A t t i tudes, in L. L i n s k y (ed.), Reference and Modality, O x f o r d U n i v e r s i t y Press, O x f o r d , 1971. [ K r i 6 3 ] K r i p k e , S. A . , Semantical Considerations on M o d a l Logic, A c t a Philosophica Fennica 1 6 , 1963, p p . 8 3 - 9 4 . [Lak93] A l l T h e y K n o w A b o u t , t o appear i n : Proc. o f the 11th N a t i o n a l Conference on A r t i f i c i a l I n telligence ( A A A I - 9 3 ) , W a s h i n g t o n D C , 1993. [Lev90] Levesque, H. J . , A l l I K n o w : A S t u d y in A u toepistemic Logic, A r t i f i c i a l Intelligence, N o r t h H o l l a n d , 4 2 , 1990, p p . 2 6 3 - 3 0 9 . [Moo85] M o o r e , R., S e m a n t i c a l Considerations on N o n m o n o t o n i c Logic, A r t i f i c i a l Intelligence 2 5 , 1985, p p . 7 5 - 9 4 . [ M o r 9 0 ] M o r g e n s t e r n , L., A T h e o r y of M u l t i p l e Agent N o n m o n o t o n i c Reasoning, i n Proc. o f A A A I - 9 0 , 1990, p p . 5 3 8 - 5 4 4 . [ M G 9 2 ] M o r g e n s t e r n , L. and G u e r r e i r o , R., Epistemic Logics for M u l t i p l e A g e n t N o n m o n o t o n i c Reas o n i n g ! , Symposium on F o r m a l Reasoning about Beliefs, I n t e n t i o n s , and A c t i o n s , A u s t i n , T X , 1992. [Per87] P e r r a u l t , R., A n A p p l i c a t i o n o f D e f a u l t Logic t o Speech A c t T h e o r y , in Proc. of the Symposium on I n t e n t i o n s and P l a n s in C o m m u n i c a t i o n and Discourse, M o n t e r e y , 1987. [Sta80] Stalnaker, R. C, A N o t e on N o n m o n o t o n i c M o d a l Logic, D e p a r t m e n t o f Philosophy, Cornell U n i v e r s i t y , 1980. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Joe Halpern and Hector Levesque for fruitful discussions on this subject. Lakemeyer 381
© Copyright 2024